Justice is one of the most
important moral and political concepts.
The word comes from the Latin jus, meaning right or law. The Oxford English Dictionary defines the
“just” person as one who typically “does what is morally right” and is disposed
to “giving everyone his or her due,” offering the word “fair” as a
synonym. But philosophers want to get
beyond etymology and dictionary definitions to consider, for example, the
nature of justice as both a moral virtue of character and a desirable quality
of political society, as well as how it applies to ethical and social
decision-making. This article will focus
on Western philosophical conceptions of justice. These will be the greatest theories of
ancient Greece (those of Plato and Aristotle) and of medieval Christianity
(Augustine and Aquinas), two early modern ones (Hobbes and Hume), two from more
recent modern times (Kant and Mill), and some contemporary ones (Rawls and
several successors). Typically the
article considers not only their theories of justice but also how philosophers
apply their own theories to controversial social issues—for example, to civil
disobedience, punishment, equal opportunity for women, slavery, war, property
rights, and international relations.
For Plato, justice is a
virtue establishing rational order, with each part performing its appropriate
role and not interfering with the proper functioning of other parts. Aristotle
says justice consists in what is lawful and fair, with fairness involving
equitable distributions and the correction of what is inequitable. For Augustine, the cardinal virtue of justice
requires that we try to give all people their due; for Aquinas, justice is that
rational mean between opposite sorts of injustice, involving proportional
distributions and reciprocal transactions.
Hobbes believed justice is an artificial virtue, necessary for civil
society, a function of the voluntary agreements of the social contract; for
Hume, justice essentially serves public utility by protecting property (broadly
understood). For Kant, it is a virtue
whereby we respect others’ freedom, autonomy, and dignity by not interfering
with their voluntary actions, so long as those do not violate others’ rights;
Mill said justice is a collective name for the most important social utilities,
which are conducive to fostering and protecting human liberty. Rawls analyzed justice in terms of maximum
equal liberty regarding basic rights and duties for all members of society,
with socio-economic inequalities requiring moral justification in terms of
equal opportunity and beneficial results for all; and various post-Rawlsian
philosophers develop alternative conceptions.
Western philosophers
generally regard justice as the most fundamental of all virtues for ordering
interpersonal relations and establishing and maintaining a stable political
society. By tracking the historical
interplay of these theories, what will be advocated is a developing
understanding of justice in terms of respecting persons as free, rational
agents. One may disagree about the
nature, basis, and legitimate application of justice, but this is its core. This is the contemporary thought about the subject.
Contemporary
Philosophers
We shall now consider how John
Rawls, addresses this ideal. We should
notice how he places a greater emphasis on equality than do most of his
European predecessors—perhaps reflecting the conviction of the American
Declaration of Independence that “all men are created equal.” (This greater emphasis may reflect the
influence of Marx, whom he occasionally mentions.) After considering the formidable
contributions of Rawls to justice theory and some of its applications, we shall
conclude this survey with a brief treatment of several post-Rawlsian
alternatives. A key focus that will
distinguish this section from previous ones is the effort to achieve a
conception of justice that strikes a reasonable balance between liberty and
equality.
a.
Rawls
Rawls burst into prominence
in 1958 with the publication of his game-changing paper, “Justice as
Fairness.” Though it was not his first
important publication, it revived the social contract theory that had been
languishing in the wake of Hume’s critique and its denigration by utilitarians
and pragmatists, though it was a Kantian version of it that Rawls
advocated. This led to a greatly
developed book version, A Theory of Justice, published in 1971, arguably the
most important book of American philosophy published in the second half of the
last century. Rawls makes it clear that
his theory, which he calls “justice as fairness,” assumes a Kantian view of
persons as “free and equal,” morally autonomous, rational agents, who are not
necessarily egoists. He also makes it
clear early on that he means to present his theory as a preferable alternative
to that of utilitarians. He asks us to
imagine persons in a hypothetical “initial situation” which he calls “the
original position” (corresponding to the “state of nature” or “natural
condition” of Hobbes, but clearly not presented as any sort of historical or
pre-historical fact). This is strikingly
characterized by what Rawls calls “the veil of ignorance,” a device designed to
minimize the influence of selfish bias in attempting to determine what would be
just. If you must decide on what sort of
society you could commit yourself to accepting as a permanent member and were
not allowed to factor in specific knowledge about yourself—such as your gender,
race, ethnic identity, level of intelligence, physical strength, quickness and
stamina, and so forth—then you would presumably exercise the rational choice to
make the society as fair for everyone as possible, lest you find yourself at
the bottom of that society for the rest of your life. In such a “purely hypothetical” situation,
Rawls believes that we would rationally adopt two basic principles of justice
for our society: “the first requires
equality in the assignment of basic rights and duties, while the second holds
that social and economic inequalities, for example inequalities of wealth and
authority, are just only if they result in compensating benefits for everyone,
and in particular for the least advantaged members of society.” Here we see Rawls conceiving of justice, the
primary social virtue, as requiring equal basic liberties for all citizens and
a presumption of equality even regarding socio-economic goods. He emphasizes the point that these principles
rule out as unjust the utilitarian justification of disadvantages for some on
account of greater advantages for others, since that would be rationally
unacceptable to one operating under the veil of ignorance. Like Kant, Rawls is opposed to the
teleological or consequentialist gambit of defining the right (including the
just) in terms of “maximizing the good”; he rather, like Kant, the
deontologist, is committed to a “priority of the right over the good.” Justice is not reducible to utility or
pragmatic desirability. We should notice
that the first principle of justice, which requires maximum equality of rights
and duties for all members of society, is prior in “serial or lexical order” to
the second, which specifies how socio-economic inequalities can be justified
(Theory, pp. 12-26, 31, 42-43). Again,
this is anti-utilitarian, in that no increase in socio-economic benefits for
anyone can ever justify anything less than maximum equality of rights and
duties for all. Thus, for example, if
enslaving a few members of society generated vastly more benefits for the
majority than liabilities for them, such a bargain would be categorically ruled
out as unjust.
Rawls proceeds to develop
his articulation of these two principles of justice more carefully. He reformulates the first one in terms of
maximum equal liberty, writing that “each person is to have an equal right to
the most extensive basic liberty compatible with a similar liberty for
others.” The basic liberties intended
concern such civil rights as are protected in our Constitution—free speech,
freedom of assembly, freedom of conscience, the right to private property, the
rights to vote and hold public office, freedom from arbitrary arrest and
seizure, etc. The lexical priority of
this first principle requires that it be categorical in that the only justification
for limiting any basic liberties would be to enhance other basic liberties; for
example, it might be just to limit free access of the press to a sensational
legal proceeding in order to protect the right of the accused to a fair trial. Rawls restates his second principle to
maintain that “social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they
are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone’s advantage, and (b)
attached to positions and offices open to all.”
Thus socio-economic inequalities can be justified, but only if both
conditions are met. The first condition
(a) is “the difference principle” and takes seriously the idea that every
socio-economic difference separating one member of society from others must be
beneficial to all, including the person ranked lowest. The second condition is one of “fair equality
of opportunity,” in that socio-economic advantages must be connected to
positions to which all members of society could have access. For example, the office of the presidency has
attached to it greater social prestige and income than is available to most of
us. Is that just? It can be, assuming that all of us, as
citizens, could achieve that office with its compensations and that even those
of us at or near the bottom of the socio-economic scale benefit from
intelligent, talented people accepting the awesome responsibilities of that
office. Just as the first principle must
be lexically prior to the second, Rawls also maintains that “fair opportunity
is prior to the difference principle.”
Thus, if we have to choose between equal opportunity for all and
socio-economically benefiting “the least advantaged” members of society, the
former has priority over the latter.
Most of us today might be readily sympathetic to the first principle and
the equal opportunity condition, while finding the difference principle to be
objectionably egalitarian, to the point of threatening incentives to contribute
more than is required. Rawls does
consider a “mixed conception” of justice that most of us would regard as more
attractive “arising when the principle of average utility constrained by a
certain social minimum is substituted for the difference principle, everything
else remaining unchanged.” But there
would be a problem of fairly agreeing on that acceptable social minimum, and it
would change with shifting contingent circumstances. It is curious that his own theory of “justice
as fairness” gets attacked by socialists such as Nielsen (whom we shall consider)
for sacrificing equality for the sake of liberty and by libertarians such as
Nozick (whom we shall also consider) for giving up too much liberty for the
sake of equality. Rawls briefly suggests
that his theory of justice as fairness might be applied to international
relations, in general, and to just war theory, in particular (ibid., pp. 60-65,
75, 83, 302-303, 316, 378).
Rawls applies his theory of
justice to the domestic issue of civil disobedience. No society is perfectly just. A generally or “nearly just society” can have
unjust laws, in which case its citizens may or may not have a duty to comply
with them, depending on how severely unjust they are. If the severity of the injustice is not
great, then respect for democratic majority rule might morally dictate
compliance. Otherwise, citizens can feel
a moral obligation to engage in civil disobedience, which Rawls defines as “a
public, nonviolent, conscientious yet political act contrary to law usually
done with the aim of bringing about a change in the law or policies of the government.” Certain conditions must be met in order that
an act of civil disobedience be justified:
(1) it should normally address violations of equal civil liberties (the
first principle of justice) and/or of “fair equality of opportunity” (the
second part of the second principle), with violations of the difference
principle (the first part of the second principle) being murkier and, thus,
harder to justify; (2) the act of civil disobedience should come only after
appeals to the political majority have been reasonably tried and failed; (3) it
must seem likely to accomplish more good than harm for the social order. Yet, even if all three of these conditions
seem to be met and the disobedient action seems right, there remains the
practical question of whether it would be “wise or prudent,” under the
circumstances, to engage in the act of civil disobedience. Ultimately, every individual must decide for
himself or herself whether such action is morally and prudentially justifiable
or not as reasonably and responsibly as possible. The acts of civil disobedience of Martin
Luther King (to whom Rawls refers in a footnote) seem to have met all the
conditions, to have been done in the name of justice, and to have been morally
justified (ibid., pp. 350-357, 363-367, 372-376, 389-390, 364n).
Rawls’s second book was
Political Liberalism. Here he works out
how a just political conception might develop a workable “overlapping
consensus” despite the challenges to social union posed by a pluralism of
“reasonable comprehensive doctrines.”
This, of course, calls for some explanation. A just society must protect basic liberties
equally for all of its members, including freedom of thought and its necessary
condition, freedom of expression. But,
in a free society that protects these basic liberties, a pluralism of views and
values is likely to develop, such that people can seriously disagree about
matters they hold dear. They will
develop their own “comprehensive doctrines,” or systems of beliefs that may
govern all significant aspects of their lives.
These may be religious (like Christianity) or philosophical (like
Kantianism) or moral (like utilitarian).
Yet a variety of potentially conflicting comprehensive doctrines may be
such that all are reasonable. In such a
case, social unity requires respect for and tolerance of other sets of
beliefs. It would be unjust deliberately
to suppress reasonable comprehensive doctrines merely because they are
different from our own. The problem of
political liberalism nowadays is how we can establish “a stable and just
society whose free and equal citizens are deeply divided by conflicting and
even incommensurable religious, philosophical, and moral doctrines.” What is needed is a shared “political
conception of justice” that is neutral regarding competing comprehensive
doctrines. This could allow for “an
overlapping consensus of reasonable comprehensive doctrines,” such that
tolerance and mutual respect are operative even among those committed to incompatible
views and values, so long as they are reasonable (Liberalism, pp. 291-292,
340-342, 145, xviii, 13, 152n., 59-60, 133, 154-155, 144, 134). Thus, for example, a Christian Kantian and an
atheistic utilitarian, while sincerely disagreeing on many ethical principles,
philosophical ideas, and religious beliefs, can unite in mutually accepting,
for instance, the American Constitution as properly binding on all of us
equally. This agreement will enable them
mutually to participate in social cooperation, the terms of which are fair and
reciprocal and which can contribute to the reasonable good of the entire
society.
Near the end of his life,
Rawls published The Law of Peoples, in which he tried to apply his theory of
justice to international relations.
Given that not all societies act justly and that societies have a right
to defend themselves against aggressive violent force, there can be a right to
go to war (jus ad bellum). Yet even
then, not all is fair in war, and rules of just warfare (jus in bello) should
be observed: (1) the goal must be a
“just and lasting peace”; (2) it must be waged in defense of freedom and
security from aggression; (3) reasonable attempts must be made not to attack
innocent non-combatants; (4) the human rights of enemies (for example, against
being tortured) must be respected; (5) attempts should be made to establish
peaceful relations; and (6) practical tactics must always remain within the
parameters of moral principles. After
hostilities have ceased, just conquerors must treat their conquered former
enemies with respect—not, for example, enslaving them or denying them civil
liberties. Rawls adds a very
controversial “supreme emergency exemption” in relation to the third rule—when
a relatively just society’s very survival is in desperate peril, its attacking
enemy civilian populations, as by bombing cities, can be justifiable. More generally, Rawls applies his theory of
justice to international relations, generating eight rules regarding how the
people of other societies must be treated.
While we do not have time to explore them all here, the last one is
sufficiently provocative to be worth our considering: “Peoples have a duty to assist other peoples
living under unfavorable conditions that prevent their having a just or decent
political and social regime.” This, of
course, goes beyond not exploiting, cheating, manipulating, deceiving, and
interfering with others to a positive duty of trying to help them, at the cost
of time, money, and other resources.
Justice demands that we try to assist what Rawls calls “burdened
societies,” so that doing so is not morally supererogatory. What is most interesting here is what Rawls
refuses to say. While different peoples,
internationally speaking, might be imagined in an original position under the
veil of ignorance, and Rawls would favor encouraging equal liberties and
opportunities for all, he refuses to apply the difference principle globally in
such a way as to indicate that justice requires a massive redistribution of
wealth from richer to poorer societies (Peoples, pp. 94-96, 98-99, 37, 106,
114-117).
From a critical perspective,
Rawls’s theory of civil disobedience is excellent, as are his theory of
political liberalism and his version of the just war theory, except for that
“supreme emergency exemption,” which uncharacteristically tries to make right a
function of teleological good. His views
on international aid seem so well worked out that, ironically, they call into
question part of his general theory of justice itself. It does not seem plausible that the
difference principle should apply intrasocietally but not internationally. The problem may be with the difference
principle itself. It is not at all clear
that rational agents in a hypothetical original position would adopt such an
egalitarian principle. The veil of
ignorance leading to this controversial principle can itself be questioned as
artificial and unrealistic; one might object that, far from being
methodologically neutral, it sets up a bias (towards, for example, being
risk-aversive) that renders Rawls’s own favored principles of justice almost a
foregone conclusion. Indeed, the “mixed
conception” that Rawls himself considers and rejects seems more plausible and
more universally applicable—keeping the first principle and the second part of
the second but replacing the difference principle with one of average utility,
constrained by some social minimum, adjustable with changing
circumstances. Thus we could
satisfactorily specify the requirements of an essentially Kantian conception of
justice, as requiring respect for the dignity of all persons as free and equal,
rational moral agents. While less
egalitarian than what Rawls offers, it might prove an attractive
alternative. To what extent should
liberty be constrained by equality in a just society? This is a central issue that divides him from
many post-Rawlsians, to a few of whom we now briefly turn.
b.
Post-Rawls
Rawls’s monumental work on
justice theory revitalized political philosophy in the United States and other
English-speaking countries. In this
final subsection, we shall briefly survey some of the most important recent
attempts to provide preferable alternatives to Rawls’s conception of
justice. They will represent six
different approaches. We shall consider,
in succession, (1) the libertarian approach of Robert Nozick, (2) the
socialistic one of Kai Nielsen, (3) the communitarian one of Michael Sandel,
(4) the globalist one of Thomas Pogge, (5) the feminist one of Martha Nussbaum,
and (6) the rights-based one of Michael Boylan.
As this is merely a quick survey, we shall not delve much into the
details of their theories (limiting ourselves to a single work by each) or
explore their applications or do much in the way of a critique of them. But the point will be to get a sense of several
recent approaches to developing views of justice in the wake of Rawls.
(1) Nozick
Nozick (a departmental
colleague of Rawls at Harvard) was one of the first and remains one of the most
famous critics of Rawls’s liberal theory of justice. Both are fundamentally committed to
individual liberty. But as a
libertarian, Nozick is opposed to compromising individual liberty in order to
promote socio-economic equality and advocates a “minimal state” as the only sort
that can be socially just. In Anarchy,
State, and Utopia (1974), especially in its famous chapter on “Distributive
Justice,” while praising Rawls’s first book as the most important “work in
political and moral philosophy” since that of Mill, Nozick argues for what he calls an “entitlement conception
of justice” in terms of three principles of just holdings. First, anyone who justly acquires any holding
is rightly entitled to keep and use it.
Second, anyone who acquires any holding by means of a just transfer of
property is rightly entitled to keep and use it. It is only through some combination of these
two approaches that anyone is rightly entitled to any holding. But some people acquire holdings
unjustly—e.g., by theft or fraud or force—so that there are illegitimate
holdings. So, third, justice can require
the rectification of unjust past acquisitions.
These three principles of just holdings—“the principle of acquisition of
holdings, the principle of transfer of holdings, and the principle of rectification
of the violations of the first two principles”—constitute the core of Nozick’s
libertarian entitlement theory of justice.
People should be entitled to use their own property as they see fit, so
long as they are entitled to it. On this
view, any pattern of distribution, such as Rawls’s difference principle, that
would force people to give up any holdings to which they are entitled in order
to give it to someone else (i.e., a redistribution of wealth) is unjust. Thus, for Nozick, any state, such as ours or
one Rawls would favor, that is “more extensive” than a minimal state and
redistributes wealth by taxing those who are relatively well off to benefit the
disadvantaged necessarily “violates people’s rights” (State, pp. 149, 183, 230,
150-153, 230-231, 149).
(2) Nielsen
Nielsen, as a socialist
(against both Rawls and Nozick) considers equality to be a more fundamental
ideal than individual liberty; this is more in keeping with Marxism than with
the liberal/libertarian tradition that has largely stemmed from Locke. (Whereas capitalism supports the ownership
and control of the means of producing and distribution material goods by
private capital or wealth, socialism holds that they should be owned and
controlled by society as a whole.) If
Nozick accuses Rawls of going too far in requiring a redistribution of wealth,
Nielsen criticizes him for favoring individual liberty at the expense of social
equality. In direct contrast to Rawls’s
two liberal principles of justice, in “Radical Egalitarian Justice: Justice as Equality,” Nielsen proposes his
own two socialistic principles constituting the core of his “egalitarian
conception of justice.” In his first
principle, he calls for “equal basic liberties and opportunities” (rather than
for merely “equal basic liberties”), including the opportunities “for
meaningful work, for self-determination, and political participation,” which he
considers important to promote “equal moral autonomy and equal
self-respect.” Also (unlike Rawls) he
does not claim any lexical priority for either principle over the other. His sharper departure from Rawls can be found
in his second principle, which is to replace the difference principle that
allegedly justified socio-economic inequality.
After specifying a few qualifications, it calls for “the income and
wealth” of society “to be so divided that each person will have a right to an
equal share” and for the burdens of society “also to be equally shared,
subject, of course, to limitations by differing abilities and differing
situations.” He argues that his own
second principle would better promote “equal self-respect and equal moral
autonomy” among the members of society.
Thus we might eliminate social stratification and class exploitation, in
accordance with the ideals of Marxist humanism (“Equality,” pp. 209, 211-213,
222-225).
(3) Sandel
Sandel, as a communitarian,
argues (against Rawls and Nozick) that the well-being of a community takes
precedence over individual liberty and (against Nielsen) over the
socio-economic welfare of its members. While
acknowledging that Rawls is not so “narrowly individualistic” as to rule out
the value of building social community, in Liberalism and the Limits of
Justice, he maintains that the individualism of persons in the original
position is such that “a sense of community” is not a basic “constituent of
their identify as such,” so that community is bound to remain secondary and
derivative in the Rawlsian theory. To
deny that community values help constitute one’s personal identity is to render
impossible any preexisting interpersonal good from which a sense of right can
be derived. Thus, for Sandel, Rawls’s
myopic theory of human nature gives him no basis for any pre-political natural
rights. So his conception of justice
based on this impoverished view must fail to reflect “the shared
self-understandings” of who they are as members of community that must
undergird the basic structure of political society. Through the interpersonal relationships of
community, we establish “more or less enduring attachments and commitments”
that help define who we are, as well as the values that will help characterize
our sense of justice as a common good that cannot be properly understood by
individuals detached from community.
Thus justice must determine what is right as serving the goods we
embrace in a social context—“as members of this family or community or nation
or people, as bearers of this history, as sons and daughters of that
revolution, as citizens of this republic” rather than as abstract individuals
(Limits, pp. 66, 60-65, 87, 150, 172-174, 179, 183, 179).
(4) Pogge
Pogge develops a globalist
interpretation of justice as fairness that, in a sense, is more consistent than
Rawls’s own. More specifically, it not
only accepts the difference principle but wants to apply it on an international
level as well as nationally. In “An
Egalitarian Law of Peoples,” Pogge observes that Rawls means his theory of
justice to be relatively “egalitarian.”
And, as applied intranationally, so it is. But, as applied internationally, it is
not. As he says, there is a disconnect
“between Rawls’s conception of domestic and of global justice.” (We should note that, like Sandel’s critique,
which we just considered, Pogge’s is not a complete theory of justice, but more
a modification of Rawls’s own.) While
Rawls does believe that well-off societies have a duty to assist burdened
societies, he rejects the idea of a global application of his difference
principle. What Pogge is proposing is a
global egalitarian principle of distributive justice. He thinks that this will address
socio-economic equalities that are to the detriment of the world’s worst-off
persons. What he proposes is “a global
resources tax, or GRT.” This means that,
although each of the peoples of our planet “owns and fully controls all
resources within its national territory,” it will be taxed on all of the
resources it extracts. If it uses those
extracted resources itself, it must pay the tax itself. If it sells some to other societies,
presumably at least part of the tax burden will be borne by buyers in the form
of higher sales prices. “The GRT is then
a tax on consumption” of our planet’s resources. Corporations extracting resources (such as
oil companies and coal mining companies) would pay their taxes to their
governments which, in turn, would be responsible for transferring funds to
disadvantaged societies to help the global poor. Such payments should be regarded as “a matter
of entitlement rather than charity,” an obligation of international
justice. If the governments of the
poorer states were honest, they could disburse the funds; if they were corrupt,
then transfers could go through United Nations agencies and/or nongovernmental
organizations. At any rate, they should
be channeled toward societies in which they could improve the lot of the poor
and disadvantaged. (Of course, less
well-off societies would be free to refuse such funds, if they so chose.) But, one might wonder, would well-off
societies only be motivated to pay their fair share by benevolence, a sense of
justice, and possible shame at being exposed for not doing so? No, there could be international
sanctions: “Once the agency facilitating
the flow of GRT payments reports that a country has not met its obligations
under the scheme, all other countries are required to impose duties on imports
from, and perhaps also similar levies on exports to, this country to raise
funds equivalent to its GRT obligations plus the cost of these enforcement
measures.” Pogge believes that well-off
societies should recognize that his more egalitarian model of international
relations is also more just than Rawls’s law of peoples (“Egalitarian,” pp.
195-196, 210, 199-202, 205, 219, 224).
(5) Nussbaum
Nussbaum, like Pogge (and
unlike Nozick and Nielsen), does not so much reject Rawls’s liberal conception
of justice as extend its explicit application.
In Sex and Social Justice, she argues for a feminist interpretation of
justice, using what she calls a “capabilities approach” that connects with “the
tradition of Kantian liberalism,” nowadays represented by Rawls, tapping into
their “notions of dignity and liberty,” as a foundation for discussing the
demands of justice regarding “women’s equality and women’s human rights.” The feminism she embraces has five key
dimensions: (1) an internationalism,
such that it is not limited to any one particular culture; (2) a humanism, such
as affirms a basic equal worth in all human beings and promotes justice for
all; (3) a commitment to liberalism as the perspective that best protects and
promotes the “basic human capacities for choice and reasoning” that render all
humans as having an equal worth; (4) a sensitivity to the cultural shaping of
our preferences and desires; and (5) a concern for sympathetic understanding
between the sexes. She expresses an
appreciation for the primary goods at the core of Rawls’s theory, while
asserting that his analysis does not go far enough. She offers her own list of ten “central human
functional capabilities” that must be respected by a just society: (1) life of a normal, natural duration; (2)
bodily health and integrity, including adequate nourishment and shelter; (3)
bodily integrity regarding, for example, freedom of movement and security
against assault; (4) freedom to exercise one’s senses, imagination, and thought
as one pleases, which includes freedom of expression; (5) freedom to form
emotional attachments to persons and things, which includes freedom of
association; (6) the development and exercise of practical reason, the capacity
to form one’s own conception of the good and to try to plan one’s own life,
which includes the protection of freedom of conscience; (7) freedom of
affiliation on equal terms with others, which involves provisions of
nondiscrimination; (8) concern for and possible relationships with animals,
plants, and the world of nature; (9) the freedom to play, to seek amusement,
and to enjoy recreational activities; and (10) some control over one’s own
political environment, including the right to vote, and one’s material
environment, including the rights to seek meaningful work and to hold
property. All of these capabilities are
essential to our functioning as flourishing human beings and should be assured
for all citizens of a just society. But,
historically, women have been and still are short-changed with respect to them
and should be guaranteed their protection in the name of justice (Sex, pp. 24,
6-14, 34, 40-42).
(6) Boylan
Boylan has recently
presented “a ‘rights-based’ deontological approach based upon the necessary
conditions for human action.” In A Just
Society, he observes that human goods are more or less deeply “embedded” as
conditions of human action, leading to a hierarchy that can be set forth. There are two levels of basic goods. The most deeply embedded of these, such as
food, clothing, shelter, protection from physical harm, are absolutely
necessary for any meaningful human action.
The second level of basic goods comprises (less) deeply embedded ones,
such as basic knowledge and skills such as are imparted by education, social
structures that allow us to trust one another, basic assurance that we will not
be exploited, and the protection of basic human rights. Next, there are three levels of secondary
goods. The most embedded of these are life
enhancing, if not necessary for any meaningful action, such as respect, equal
opportunity, and the capacity to form and follow one’s own plan of life and to
participate actively and equally in community, characterized by shared values. A second level of secondary goods comprises
those that are useful for human action, such as having and being able to use
property, being able to benefit from one’s own labor, and being able to pursue
goods typically owned by most of one’s fellow citizens. The third level of secondary goods comprises
those that are least embedded as conditions of meaningful action but still
desirable as luxuries, such as being able to seek pleasant objectives that most
of one’s fellow citizens cannot expect to achieve and being able to compete for
somewhat more than others in one’s society.
The more deeply embedded goods are as conditions of meaningful human
action, the more right to them people have.
Boylan follows Kant and Rawls in holding an ultimate moral imperative is
that individual human agents and their rights must be respected. This is a matter of justice, distributive
justice involving a fair distribution of social goods and services and
retributive justice involving proper ways for society to treat those who
violate the rules. A just society has a
duty to provide basic goods equally to all of its members, if it can do
so. But things get more complicated with
regards to secondary goods. A just
society will try to provide the first level of secondary goods, those that are
life enhancing, equally to all its members.
Yet this becomes more problematic with the second and third levels of
secondary goods—those that are useful and luxurious—as the conditions for
meaningful human action have already been satisfied by more deeply embedded
ones. The need that people have to
derive rewards for their work commensurate with their achievement would seem to
militate against any guarantee of equal shares in these, even if society could
provide them, although comparable achievement should be comparably
rewarded. Finally, in the area of
retributive justice, we may briefly consider three scenarios. First, when one person takes a tangible good
from another person, justice requires that the perpetrator return to the victim
some tangible good(s) of comparable worth, plus compensation proportionate to
the harm done the victim by the loss.
Second, when one person takes an intangible good from another person,
justice requires that the perpetrator give the victim some tangible good as
adequate compensation for the pain and suffering caused by the loss. And, third, when one person injures another
person through the deprivation of a valued good that negatively affects
society, society can justly incarcerate the perpetrator for a period of time
proportionate to the loss (Society, pp. x, 53-54, 56-58, 131, 138, 143-144,
164-167, 174-175, 181, 183).
In conclusion, we might
observe that, in this rights-based alternative, as in the previous five (the
libertarian, the socialistic, the communitarian, the globalist, and the
feminist) we have considered, there is an attempt to interpret justice as
requiring respect for the dignity of all persons as free and equal, rational
moral agents. This survey has tracked
the progressive development of this Kantian idea as becoming increasingly
prominent in Western theories of justice.
No comments:
Post a Comment