In two works, a paper in The
Journal of Symbolic Logic in 1946 and the book Meaning and Necessity in 1947,
Rudolf Carnap developed a modal predicate logic containing a necessity operator
N, whose semantics depends on the claim that, where α is a formula of the
language, Nα represents the proposition that α is logically necessary. Carnap’s
view was that Nα should be true if and only if α itself is logically valid, or,
as he put it, is L-true. In the light of the criticisms of modal logic
developed by W.V. Quine from 1943 on, the challenge for Carnap was how to
produce a theory of validity for modal predicate logic in a way which enables
an answer to be given to these criticisms. This article discusses Carnap’s
motivation for developing a modal logic in the first place; and it then looks
at how the modal predicate logic developed in his 1946 paper might be adapted
to answer Quine’s objections. The adaptation is then compared with the way in
which Carnap himself tried to answer Quine’s complaints in the 1947 book.
Particular attention is paid to the problem of how to treat the meaning of
formulas which contain a free individual variable in the scope of a modal
operator, that is, to the problem of how to handle what Quine called the third
grade of ‘modal involvement’.
In an important article
(Carnap 1946) and in a book a year later, (Carnap 1947), Rudolf Carnap
articulated a system of modal logic. Carnap took himself to be doing two
things; the first was to develop an account of the meaning of modal expressions;
the second was to extend it to apply to what he called “modal functional logic”
— that is, what we would call modal predicate logic or modal first-order logic.
Carnap distinguishes between a logic or a ‘semantical system’, and a
‘calculus’, which is an axiomatic system, and states on p. 33 of 1946 that “So far, no forms of MFC [modal functional
calculus] have been constructed, and the construction of such a system is our
chief aim.” In fact, in the preceding issue of The Journal of Symbolic Logic,
the first presentation of Ruth Barcan’s axiomatic systems of modal predicate
logic had already appeared, although they contained only an axiomatic
presentation. (Barcan 1946.) The principal importance of Carnap’s work is thus
his attempt to produce a semantics for modal predicate logic, and it is that
concern that this article will focus on.
Nevertheless, first-order
logic is founded on propositional logic, and Carnap first looks at non-modal
propositional logic and modal propositional logic. I shall follow Carnap in
using ~ and ∨ for
negation and disjunction, though I shall use ∧ in place of Carnap’s ‘.’ for conjunction.
Carnap takes these as primitive together with ‘t’ which stands for an arbitrary
tautologous sentence. He recognises that ∧ and
t can be defined in terms of ~ and ∨,
but prefers to take them as primitive because of the importance to his
presentation of conjunctive normal form. Carnap adopts the standard definitions
of ⊃ and ≡. I will, however,
deviate from Carnap’s notation by using Greek in place of German letters for
metalinguistic symbols. In place of ‘valid’ Carnap speaks of L-true, and in
place of ‘unsatisfiable’, L-false. α L-implies β iff (if and only if) α ⊃ β is valid. α and β are
L-equivalent iff α ≡ β is valid.
One might at this stage ask
what led Carnap to develop a modal logic at all. The clue here seems to be the
influence of Wittgenstein. In his philosophical autobiography Carnap writes:
For me personally,
Wittgenstein was perhaps the philosopher who, besides Russell and Frege, had
the greatest influence on my thinking. The most important insight I gained from
his work was the conception that the truth of logical statements is based only
on their logical structure and on the meaning of the terms. Logical statements
are true under all conceivable circumstances; thus their truth is independent
of the contingent facts of the world. On the other hand, it follows that these
statements do not say anything about the world and thus have no factual
content. (Carnap 1963, p. 25)
Wittgenstein’s account of
logical truth depended on the view that every (cognitively meaningful) sentence
has truth conditions. (Wittgenstein 1921, 4.024.) Carnap certainly appears to
have taken Wittgenstein’s remark as endorsing the truth-conditional theory of
meaning. (See for instance Carnap 1947 p. 9.) If all logical truths are
tautologies, and all tautologies are contentless, then you don’t need
metaphysics to explain (logical) necessity.
One of the features of
Wittgenstein’s view was that any way the world could be is determined by a
collection of particular facts, where each such fact occupies a definite
position in logical space, and where the way that position is occupied is
independent of the way any other position of logical space is occupied. Such a
world may be described in a logically perfect language, in which each atomic
formula describes how a position of logical space is occupied. So suppose that
we begin with this language, and instead of asking whether it reflects the
structure of the world, we ask whether it is a useful language for describing
the world. From Carnap’s perspective, (Carnap 1950) one might describe it in
such a way as this. Given a language £ we may ask whether £ is adequate, or
perhaps merely useful, for describing the world as we experience it. It is
incoherent to speak about what the world in itself is like without presupposing
that one is describing it. What makes £ a Carnapian equivalent of a logically
perfect language would be that each of its atomic sentences is logically
independent of any other atomic sentence, and that every possible world can be
described by a state-description.
No comments:
Post a Comment