Traditionally, there were
two opposing philosophical positions taken with respect to the legitimacy of
the ethical evaluation of art: ‘moralism’ and ‘autonomism’, where moralism is
the view that the aesthetic value of art should be determined by, or reduced
to, its moral value, while autonomism holds that it is inappropriate to apply
moral categories to art; they should be evaluated by ‘aesthetic’ standards
alone. Recent work on the ethical criticism of art has proposed several new
positions; more moderate versions of autonomism and moralism which lie between
the two extremes described above. The issue has now become not one of whether
moral evaluations of art works are appropriate, but rather, whether they should
be described as aesthetic evaluations. The contemporary debate focuses on
narrative art, which is seen as having unique features to which ethical
criticism is particularly pertinent. Attempts have been made to simplify the
issue of the ethical criticism of art by distancing peripheral issues such as
causal claims about the effects of art on its audience and censorship. However,
there is still considerable interest in the possibility of certain narrative
artworks having the potential to play an important role in moral education. The
debate over the ethical criticism of art therefore highlights some of the
central reasons why we value narrative art, as well as questioning the scope,
or the parameters, of our concept of the aesthetic.
Introduction
‘Ethical criticism’ refers
to the inclusion of an ethical component in the interpretation and evaluation
of art. The two traditional opposing positions taken with respect to ethical
criticism are ‘autonomism’ and ‘moralism’. The former claims that ethical
criticism is never legitimate since moral and aesthetic value are autonomous,
while the latter reduces aesthetic value to moral value. The extreme versions
of autonomism and moralism, their appeal and their flaws, are discussed in
section two.
In recent years, debate over
ethical criticism has resurfaced, partly through the Ethical Criticism
Symposium featured in Philosophy and Literature in 1997-8, which is discussed
in the final section of this article, since it bears on the consideration of
the causal thesis that certain literature can have positive moral effects on
its audience. A second arm of the ethical criticism debate saw several more
moderate, and more plausible, positions proposed. These are ‘moderate
autonomism’, ‘moderate moralism’ and ‘ethicism’. In this body of literature
too, the focus was on narrative art. What is at issue in the current debate is
whether the realm of aesthetic value should be taken to include the moral value
of narrative art (a) never, (b) only sometimes when an artwork displays moral
features (merits or defects), or (c) whenever an artwork displays moral
features (merits or defects). Due to differences between the modes of
expression and content matter of the different art forms, it seems likely that
what is true of the ethical criticism of narrative art, which often deals explicitly
with human affairs and morality, may not be true of abstract art forms such as
music and some fine arts and dance. Such art forms would require separate
consideration and this is something which has not thus far been undertaken in
the philosophical literature.
Section 3 considers the
debate between moderate autonomism, defended by Anderson and Dean, and Noel
Carroll’s moderate moralism, examining Carroll’s reasons for arguing that at
least sometimes the moral features of narrative artworks are also aesthetic
features. Section 4 introduces Berys Gaut’s ‘ethicism’, and examines the
contention, made primarily by Anderson and Dean, that moderate moralism and
ethicism are one and the same position. This claim is shown to be false, and
the two positions are clearly distinguished. Much of the recent debate over
ethical criticism – that is the debate between moderate autonomism, moderate
moralism and ethicism – focusses on the flaws in the specific arguments
presented for moderate moralism and ethicism. In fact, the central issue in the
debate over ethical criticism, which is somewhat masked by the details, is how
broadly the aesthetic should be defined. While the extreme positions, radical
autonomism and radical moralism define the aesthetic most narrowly, the
position which defines the aesthetic most broadly and inclusively is ethicism.
Radical
Autonomism and Radical Moralism
There are two extreme
positions traditionally taken with respect to the relationship between art and
morality; one is autonomism, or aestheticism, which is the view that it is
inappropriate to apply moral categories to artworks, and that only aesthetic
categories are relevant, while at the other end of the scale is moralism, the
view that aesthetic objects should be judged wholly or centrally with respect
to moral standards or values. Both autonomism and moralism are widely
recognised to be problematic, as they are based on inadequate conceptions of
art and aesthetic value.
Radical Moralism is the view
that the aesthetic value of an artwork is determined by its moral value. The
most extreme version of this position reduces all aesthetic value to moral
value. Proponents of radical moralism include Tolstoy, who, arguing against
definitions of art that equated art with beauty, said: “The inaccuracy of all
these definitions arises from the fact that in them all … the object considered
is the pleasure art may give, and not the purpose it may serve in the life of
man and of humanity.” Tolstoy emphasised the moral significance of art in society
as essential to the (aesthetic) value of art. Social reductionism, such as the
‘popular aesthetic’ endorsed by Pierre Bourdieu, Roger Taylor and others, is
also a version of radical moralism. Radical moralism has been widely criticised
for ignoring certain fundamental aspects of aesthetic value, such as formal
features. The radical moralist will have some difficulty explaining how art can
be distinguished from other cultural products, including such things as
political speeches, due to their failure to include in their criteria for
making judgments about aesthetic value anything that is a unique feature of
art.
Autonomism and aestheticism
are essentially the same position. The label ‘autonomism’ captures the fact
that this position holds that aesthetic value is autonomous from other kinds of
value, such as moral value. The label ‘aestheticism’ captures the fact that the
position emphasises the importance of focussing on theaesthetic, that is, the
pure aesthetic, features of artworks. Pure aesthetic qualities may include
formal features and beauty or, for some autonomists, formal features only. It
is important to note that formalism and autonomism are not identical positions,
although advocates of formalism will tend to be autonomists. Formalism, rejected
earlier, is the view that the proper way to respond to art is to respond to its
formal features or, in other words, that the aesthetic value of an artwork is
determined solely by its formal features. A formalist, such as Clive Bell,
would not include beauty as something we should respond to in art, but those
formalists who do include beauty regard it as something that is determined by
the formal features the artwork possesses.
“Aestheticism’ is perhaps
the more appropriate label for the extreme position subscribed to by the
aesthete – that aesthetic value is the highest of all values. Interestingly,
although the aesthete might not be interested in defending their position, any
attempt to do so would likely involve appeals to moral standards; that is, they
would have to give a justification for their view that one should take on a
predominantly aesthetic attitude in life in terms of moral value. For example,
Richard Posner, in ‘Against Ethical Criticism’, appears to identify himself as
an aesthete, but, ironically, an aesthete who wants to provide a moral
justification for his position: “The aesthetic outlook is a moral outlook, one
that stresses the values of openness, detachment, hedonism, curiosity,
tolerance, the cultivation of the self, and the preservation of a private
sphere – in short, the values of liberal individualism.”(1997, p. 2)
Aestheticism, in it’s most extreme form, could almost be seen as a version of
radical moralism. In any case, both positions are equally reductive with
respect to the scope of aesthetic value.
Moderate
Autonomism and Moderate Moralism
Moderate Autonomism
Moderate autonomism,
defended by J. Anderson and J. Dean, is a more plausible position than radical
autonomism; it recognises that moral merits or defects can feature in the
content of certain art forms and that sometimes moral judgments of artworks are
pertinent. However, moderate autonomism is still an autonomist position in the
sense that it maintains that the aesthetic value and the moral value of
artworks are autonomous. According to moderate autonomism: “an artwork will
never be aesthetically better in virtue of its moral strengths, and will never
be worse because of its moral defects. / On a strict reading of moderate
autonomism, one of its decisive claims is that defective moral understanding never
counts against the aesthetic merit of a work. An artwork may invite an audience
to entertain a defective moral perspective and this will not detract from its
aesthetic value.”(Carroll, 1996, p. 232) It is this central claim that both
Carroll and Gaut argue against.
Moderate Moralism
Moderate autonomism stands
in opposition to ‘Moderate moralism’: “[Moderate moralism] contends that some
works of art may be evaluated morally (contra radical autonomism) and that
sometimes the moral defects and/or merits of a work may figure in the aesthetic
evaluation of the work.” (p. 236) The crucial difference between moderate
autonomism and moderate moralism, then, is that while both agree that moral
judgments can be legitimately made about certain artworks, moderate moralists
contend that sometimes such judgments are aesthetic evaluations, while moderate
autonomists hold that moral judgments about works of art are always outside the
realm of the aesthetic. On the one hand, Anderson and Dean say, “some of the
knowledge that art brings home to us may be moral knowledge. All this is
granted when we agree that art is properly subject to moral evaluation. But why
is this value aesthetic value?” (Anderson & Dean p. 160) On the other hand,
Carroll says, “Moderate autonomists overlook the degree to which moral
presuppositions play a structural role in the design of many artworks.”(Carroll
1996 p. 233) Carroll does not suggest that this is the only way in which moral
features may contribute to a work’s aesthetic value; a more general account of
this is described in the following section.
Moderate
Autonomism vs Moderate Moralism
What is really at issue in
the debate over ethical criticism is how broadly we define the aesthetic. But
this is not simply arbitrary – what in fact are the boundaries of the aesthetic?
Carroll aims to show, with reference to specific examples, that there are
actual cases where a narrow construal of the aesthetic, such as the one adopted
by moderate autonomists, is an inadequate way of understanding that work’s
aesthetic value, and an inadequate way of understanding how we appreciate such
artworks qua artworks. Even if moderate moralism is not the best way to explain
the moral value of narrative artworks, Carroll is wise to turn to critical
analysis of actual examples to support his argument, for this is where we can
most clearly see the problems with moderate autonomism.
The central argument for
moderate moralism (hereafter MM) is described as the ‘Common Reason Argument.’
Having first argued that many narrative artworks are incomplete in ways that
require us to use our moral understanding in order to comprehend the work,
Carroll then argues, with reference to examples, that because of this fact
about narrative artworks, it is sometimes the case that a moral defect in a
work will also be an aesthetic defect since it prevents us from fully engaging
with that work. In other words, Carroll argues that in some cases the reason a
work is morally flawed is the same reason the work is aesthetically flawed, and
so in these cases the judgment that the work is morally flawed is also an
aesthetic evaluation of that work. (Anderson & Dean, 1998, pp. 156-7) Mary
Devereaux’s analysis ofTriumph of the Will provides an excellent example of
this. (See her article ‘Beauty and Evil’ in Levinson,Aesthetics & Ethics,
1998). According to Devereaux, Triumph of the Will is morally problematic
because it presents the Nazi regime as appealing. Although a morally sensitive
audience might be able to appreciate some of the formal features exhibited in
the film, such as the innovative camera work, such an audience would be unable
to fully engage with the film due to an inability to accept the film’s central
vision, that is, the glorification of Hitler and the Nazi regime. If the
audience is unable to fully engage with the film’s central vision, this,
according to Carroll’s MM, will count as an aesthetic defect in the film
(because the magnitude of our aesthetic experience will be limited by our
inability to fully engage with the film’s central theme). So, the very feature
that makes the film morally defective is also one of most significant aesthetic
defects in the film. Hence, the moral defectiveness and the aesthetic
defectiveness are due to a common reason in this particular case.
In their argument against
MM, Anderson and Dean construct two arguments, a ‘moral defect argument’ and an
‘aesthetic defect argument’, which, together, they take to represent the
‘common reason argument.’ The two arguments are presented as follows:
The
Moral Defect Argument
1.-The perspective of the
work in question is immoral.
2.- Therefore, the work
‘invites us to share [this morally] defective perspective’ (In one case we are
invited to find an evil person sympathetic; in the other case, we are invited
to find gruesome acts humorous.)
3.- Any work which invites
us to share a morally defective perspective is, itself, morally defective.
4.- Therefore, the work in
question is morally defective
The
Aesthetic Defect Argument
1.-The perspective of the
work in question is immoral.
2.- The immorality portrayed
subverts the possibility of uptake. (In the case of the tragedy, the response
of pity is precluded; in the case of the satire the savouring of parody is
precluded.)
3.-Any work which subverts
its own genre is aesthetically defective.
4- Therefore, the work in
question is aesthetically defective. (pp. 156-7)
Anderson and Dean focus
their objection to MM on the fact that the one premise the moral defect
argument and the aesthetic defect argument share (1) is not sufficient to
establish either moral defectiveness or aesthetic defectiveness.(p. 157) This
may be so, but Carroll responds to this by pointing out the common reason
doesn’t need to be a sufficient reason. There may be other reasons that
contribute to both the aesthetic evaluation and the moral evaluation of artworks,
but in some cases these two groups of reasons overlap; where a reason is common
to both groups, and is a central, if not sufficient, reason for both the
conclusion that a work is morally defective, and the conclusion that the work
is aesthetically defective. As Carroll puts it in his response to Anderson and
Dean:
But why suppose that the
relevant sense of reason here is sufficient reason? Admittedly a number of
factors will contribute to the moral defectiveness and the aesthetic
defectiveness of the work in question. The moderate moralist need only contend
that among the complex of factors that account for the moral defectiveness of
the artwork in question, on the one hand, and the complex of factors that
explain the aesthetic defectiveness of the artwork, on the other hand, the evil
perspective of the artwork will play a central, though perhaps not sufficient,
explanatory role in both. (Carroll, 1998a, p423)
Carroll’s response to
Anderson and Dean’s objection is convincing. There seems no reason to object to
MM simply because the common reason shared the aesthetic defect argument and
the moral defect argument is not a sufficient reason in either case.
Anderson and Dean eschew
specific examples in their defense of MA, saying: ‘because of the complexity of
particular cases, we have taken pains not to rest our case on the examination
of them.” (A&D, 1998, p. 164). Since MM holds that moral judgments about
artworks can be aesthetic evaluations in some cases, it is only necessary to
show that the reason a work is morally defective is the same as the reason that
work is aesthetically defective in a few actual cases in order to support MM.
Carroll does give us some convincing examples, and Anderson and Dean do not
show why Carroll is wrong in these particular cases. Given that there are at
least some cases, such as Devereaux’s analysis of Triumph of the Will, in which
it has been convincingly shown that the reason a work is morally meritorious or
defective is the same reason that work is aesthetically meritorious or
defective, it follows that moderate autonomism is false.
However, ‘aestheticism’ does
not always refer to the extreme position, and the terms ‘autonomism’ and
‘aestheticism’ can be used interchangeably. Autonomism has become the
predominant term used in recent literature, most likely because it does capture
the notion that aesthetic value is held to be an autonomous realm of value by
those who subscribe to any version of this position. Radical Autonomism is the
view that the proper way to respond to art is to respond only to the pure aesthetic
qualities, or what is ‘in the work itself’; while to bring moral values, or
other social values, to bear on art is a mistake. The radical autonomist’s
motto is ‘art for art’s sake’. Oscar Wilde is an example of a radical
autonomist. He wrote in the Preface to The Picture of Dorien Gray: “…to art’s
subject matter we should be more or less indifferent,” and “Life is the solvent
that breaks up art, the enemy that lays waste her house.” Wilde’s statements on
the topic of and and morality are those of an autonomist, although the subject
matter of his own work dealt explicitly with moral issues. His position appears
to have been not that literary art can’t deal with moral issues as part of its
subject matter, but simply that they are irrelevant to the aesthetic value of
the art, and should not influence the audience’s, or critic’s, aesthetic
response to the work. An autonomist position such as this is based on a narrow
understanding of the aesthetic value of art, which values the way in which the
subject matter of such art is represented (which may include formal features
and beauty), but not the subject matter itself (which may include moral
features). However, autonomism, while purporting to give aesthetic value
primacy, neglects many of the potential ways in which art can have aesthetic
value. Such a view ignores the fact that certain art forms are culturally
embedded, and, as such, are inextricably bound up with important social values,
such as moral value.
Noel Carroll explains the
appeal of radical autonomism with reference to the “common denominator
argument”; that is, the argument that it is only those features common to all
art that are the essential defining features of art, and it is only these
features that should properly be regarded as being within the realm of the
aesthetic. (See ‘Moderate Moralism’, BJA, 36:3, 1996) As Carroll points out,
the fact that radical autonomists have a ready answer to the questions -What
are the unique and essential features common to all art? – or – What are the
defining features of art? – is a central reason for the appeal of their
position. This feature of autonomism appears to provide a straightforward way
of distinguishing art from non-art, as well as providing specific grounds upon
which to defend the objectivity of aesthetic value. A further reason autonomism
initially seems intuitive is that it is difficult to see how moral
considerations could be pertinent across whole art forms, such as music, and
abstract art of various kinds.(p. 226) The above reasons make radical
autonomism an attractive position, but its narrow construal of the aesthetic is
too narrow to adequately account for the aesthetic value of certain art forms,
or particular artworks. Besides, as was discussed earlier, attempting to define
art in terms of essential criteria common to all artworks is not a promising
strategy; the nature of art defies such restrictions. Carroll argues that “we
can challenge [the radical autonomist’s] appeal to the nature of art with
appeals to the natures of specific art forms or genres which, given what they
are, warrant at least additional criteria of evaluation to supplement whatever
the autonomist claims is the common denominator of aesthetic evaluation.” (p.
227)
What Carroll specifically
has in mind is the role our moral understanding plays in our appreciation of
narrative art. Carroll claims that narrative artworks are always incomplete,
and that a certain amount of information has to be filled in by the reader or
audience in order to make the work intelligible. This includes information
which must be supplied by our moral understanding. He says: “…it is vastly
improbable that there could be any substantial narrative of human affairs,
especially a narrative artwork, that did not rely upon activating the moral
powers of readers, viewers and listeners. Even modernist novels that appear to
eschew ‘morality’ typically do so in order to challenge bourgeois morality and
to enlist the reader in sharing their ethical disdain for it.” (p. 228)
Examples of works which require the input of our moral understanding in order
to make the narrative intelligible include Jane Austin’s Emma, George Elliot’s
Middlemarch, and (ironically) Oscar Wilde’s The Picture of Dorian Gray.
No comments:
Post a Comment