René Descartes:
The Mind-Body Distinction
One of the deepest and most lasting legacies of Descartes’ philosophy is
his thesis that mind and body are really distinct—a thesis now called
"mind-body dualism." He reaches this conclusion by arguing that the
nature of the mind (that is, a thinking, non-extended thing) is completely
different from that of the body (that is, an extended, non-thinking thing), and
therefore it is possible for one to exist without the other. This argument
gives rise to the famous problem of mind-body causal interaction still debated
today: how can the mind cause some of our bodily limbs to move (for example,
raising one's hand to ask a question), and how can the body’s sense organs
cause sensations in the mind when their natures are completely different? This
article examines these issues as well as Descartes’ own response to this
problem through his brief remarks on how the mind is united with the body to
form a human being. This will show how these issues arise because of a
misconception about Descartes’ theory of mind-body union, and how the correct
conception of their union avoids this version of the problem. The article
begins with an examination of the term “real distinction” and of Descartes’
probable motivations for maintaining his dualist thesis.
1. What is a Real
Distinction?
It is important to note that for Descartes “real distinction” is a
technical term denoting the distinction between two or more substances (see
Principles, part I, section 60). A substance is something that does not require
any other creature to exist—it can exist with only the help of God’s concurrence—whereas,
a mode is a quality or affection of that substance (see Principles part I,
section 5). Accordingly, a mode requires a substance to exist and not just the
concurrence of God. Being sphere shaped is a mode of an extended substance. For
example, a sphere requires an object extended in three dimensions in order to
exist: an unextended sphere cannot be conceived without contradiction. But a
substance can be understood to exist alone without requiring any other creature
to exist. For example, a stone can exist all by itself. That is, its existence
is not dependent upon the existence of minds or other bodies; and, a stone can
exist without being any particular size or shape. This indicates for Descartes
that God, if he chose, could create a world constituted by this stone all by
itself, showing further that it is a substance “really distinct” from
everything else except God. Hence, the thesis that mind and body are really
distinct just means that each could exist all by itself without any other creature,
including each other, if God chose to do it. However, this does not mean that
these substances do exist separately. Whether or not they actually exist apart
is another issue entirely.
2. Why a Real
Distinction?
A question one might ask is: what's the point of arguing that mind and
body could each exist without the other? What’s the payoff for going through
all the trouble and enduring all the problems to which it gives rise? For
Descartes the payoff is twofold. The first is religious in nature in that it
provides a rational basis for a hope in the soul’s immortality [because
Descartes presumes that the mind and soul are more or less the same thing]. The
second is more scientifically oriented, for the complete absence of mentality
from the nature of physical things is central to making way for Descartes’
version of the new, mechanistic physics. This section investigates both of
these motivating factors.
a. The Religious
Motivation
In his Letter to the Sorbonne published at the beginning of his seminal
work, Meditations on First Philosophy, Descartes states that his purpose in
showing that the human mind or soul is really distinct from the body is to
refute those “irreligious people” who only have faith in mathematics and will
not believe in the soul's immortality without a mathematical demonstration of
it. Descartes goes on to explain how, because of this, these people will not
pursue moral virtue without the prospect of an afterlife with rewards for
virtue and punishments for vice. But, since all the arguments in the
Meditations—including the real distinction arguments— are for Descartes
absolutely certain on a par with geometrical demonstrations, he believes that
these people will be obliged to accept them. Hence, irreligious people will be
forced to believe in the prospect of an afterlife. However, recall that
Descartes’ conclusion is only that the mind or soul can exist without the body.
He stops short of demonstrating that the soul is actually immortal. Indeed, in
the Synopsis to the Mediations, Descartes claims only to have shown that the
decay of the body does not logically or metaphysically imply the destruction of
the mind: further argumentation is required for the conclusion that the mind
actually survives the body's destruction. This would involve both “an account
of the whole of physics” and an argument showing that God cannot annihilate the
mind. Yet, even though the real distinction argument does not go this far, it
does, according to Descartes, provide a sufficient foundation for religion,
since the hope for an afterlife now has a rational basis and is no longer a
mere article of faith.
b. The Scientific
Motivation
The other motive for arguing that mind and body could each exist without
the other is more scientifically oriented, stemming from Descartes’ intended
replacement of final causal explanations in physics thought to be favored by
late scholastic-Aristotelian philosophers with mechanistic explanations based
on the model of geometry. Although the credit for setting the stage for this
scholastic-Aristotelian philosophy dominant at Descartes’ time should go to
Thomas Aquinas (because of his initial, thorough interpretation and
appropriation of Aristotle’s philosophy), it is also important to bear in mind
that other thinkers working within this Aristotelian framework such as Duns
Scotus, William of Ockham, and Francisco Suarez, diverged from the Thomistic
position on a variety of important issues. Indeed, by Descartes’ time,
scholastic positions divergent from Thomism became so widespread and subtle in
their differences that sorting them out was quite difficult. Notwithstanding
this convoluted array of positions, Descartes understood one thesis to stand at
the heart of the entire tradition: the doctrine that everything ultimately
behaved for the sake of some end or goal. Though these “final causes,” as they
were called, were not the only sorts of causes recognized by scholastic
thinkers, it is sufficient for present purposes to recognize that Descartes
believed scholastic natural philosophers used them as principles for physical
explanations. For this reason, a brief look at how final causes were supposed
to work is in order.
Descartes understood all scholastics to maintain that everything was
thought to have a final cause that is the ultimate end or goal for the sake of
which the rest of the organism was organized. This principle of organization
became known as a thing’s “substantial form,” because it was this principle
that explained why some hunk of matter was arranged in such and such a way so
as to be some species of substance. For example, in the case of a bird, say,
the swallow, the substantial form of swallowness was thought to organize matter
for the sake of being a swallow species of substance. Accordingly, any
dispositions a swallow might have, such as the disposition for making nests,
would then also be explained by means of this ultimate goal of being a swallow;
that is, swallows are disposed for making nests for the sake of being a swallow
species of substance. This explanatory scheme was also thought to work for
plants and inanimate natural objects.
A criticism of the traditional employment of substantial forms and their
concomitant final causes in physics is found in the Sixth Replies where
Descartes examines how the quality of gravity was used to explain a body’s
downward motion:
“ But what makes it especially
clear that my idea of gravity was taken largely from the idea I had of the mind
is the fact that I thought that gravity carried bodies toward the centre of the
earth as if it had some knowledge of the centre within itself” (AT VII 442: CSM
II 298).
On this pre-Newtonian account, a characteristic goal of all bodies was
to reach its proper place, namely, the center of the earth. So, the answer to
the question, “Why do stones fall downward?” would be, “Because they are
striving to achieve their goal of reaching the center of the earth.” According
to Descartes, this implies that the stone must have knowledge of this goal,
know the means to attain it, and know where the center of the earth is located.
But, how can a stone know anything? Surely only minds can have knowledge. Yet,
since stones are inanimate bodies without minds, it follows that they cannot
know anything at all—let alone anything about the center of the earth.
Descartes continues on to make the following point:
“But later on I made the
observations which led me to make a careful distinction between the idea of the
mind and the ideas of body and corporeal motion; and I found that all those
other ideas of . . . 'substantial forms' which I had previously held were ones
which I had put together or constructed from those basic ideas” (AT VII 442-3: CSM II 298).
Here, Descartes is claiming that the concept of a substantial form as
part of the entirely physical world stems from a confusion of the ideas of mind
and body. This confusion led people to mistakenly ascribe mental properties
like knowledge to entirely non-mental things like stones, plants, and, yes,
even non-human animals. The real distinction of mind and body can then also be
used to alleviate this confusion and its resultant mistakes by showing that
bodies exist and move as they do without mentality, and as such principles of
mental causation such as goals, purposes (that is, final causes), and knowledge
have no role to play in the explanation of physical phenomena. So the real
distinction of mind and body also serves the more scientifically oriented end
of eliminating any element of mentality from the idea of body. In this way, a
clear understanding of the geometrical nature of bodies can be achieved and
better explanations obtained.
3. The Real
Distinction Argument
Descartes formulates this argument in many different ways, which has led
many scholars to believe there are several different real distinction
arguments. However, it is more accurate to consider these formulations as
different versions of one and the same argument. The fundamental premise of
each is identical: each has the fundamental premise that the natures of mind
and body are completely different from one another.
The First Version
The first version is found in this excerpt from the Sixth Meditation:
“ [O]n the one hand I have a clear and distinct
idea of myself, in so far as I am simply a thinking, non-extended thing [that
is, a mind], and on the other hand I have a distinct idea of body, in so far as
this is simply an extended, non-thinking thing. And accordingly, it is certain
that I am really distinct from my body, and can exist without it “(AT VII 78:
CSM II 54).
Notice that the argument is given from the first person perspective (as
are the entire Meditations). This “I” is, of course, Descartes insofar as he is
a thinking thing or mind, and the argument is intended to work for any “I” or
mind. So, for present purposes, it is safe to generalize the argument by
replacing “I” with “mind” in the relevant places:
·
I
have a clear and distinct idea of the mind as a thinking, non-extended thing.
·
I
have a clear and distinct idea of body as an extended, non-thinking thing.
·
Therefore,
the mind is really distinct from the body and can exist without it.
At first glance it may seem that, without justification, Descartes is
bluntly asserting that he conceives of mind and body as two completely
different things, and that from his conception, he is inferring that he (or any
mind) can exist without the body. But this is no blunt, unjustified assertion.
Much more is at work here: most notably what is at work is his doctrine of
clear and distinct ideas and their veridical guarantee. Indeed the truth of his
intellectual perception of the natures of mind and body is supposed to be
guaranteed by the fact that this perception is “clear and distinct.” Since the
justification for these two premises rests squarely on the veridical guarantee
of whatever is “clearly and distinctly” perceived, a brief side trip explaining
this doctrine is in order.
Descartes explains what he means by a “clear and distinct idea” in his
work Principles of Philosophy at part I, section 45. Here he likens a clear
intellectual perception to a clear visual perception. So, just as someone might
have a sharply focused visual perception of something, an idea is clear when it
is in sharp intellectual focus. Moreover, an idea is distinct when, in addition
to being clear, all other ideas not belonging to it are completely excluded
from it. Hence, Descartes is claiming in both premises that his idea of the
mind and his idea of the body exclude all other ideas that do not belong to
them, including each other, and all that remains is what can be clearly
understood of each. As a result, he clearly and distinctly understands the mind
all by itself, separately from the body, and the body all by itself, separately
from the mind.
According to Descartes, his ability to clearly and distinctly understand
them separately from one another implies that each can exist alone without the
other. This is because “[e]xistence is contained in the idea or concept of
every single thing, since we cannot conceive of anything except as existing.
Possible or contingent existence is contained in the concept of a limited
thing...” (AT VII 166: CSM II 117). Descartes, then, clearly and distinctly
perceives the mind as possibly existing all by itself, and the body as possibly
existing all by itself. But couldn't Descartes somehow be mistaken about his
clear and distinct ideas? Given the existence of so many non-thinking bodies
like stones, there is no question that bodies can exist without minds. So, even
if he could be mistaken about what he clearly and distinctly understands, there
is other evidence in support of premise 2. But can minds exist without bodies?
Can thinking occur without a brain? If the answer to this question is “no,” the
first premise would be false and, therefore, Descartes would be mistaken about one
of his clear and distinct perceptions. Indeed, since we have no experience of
minds actually existing without bodies as we do of bodies actually existing
without minds, the argument will stand only if Descartes’ clear and distinct
understanding of the mind’s nature somehow guarantees the truth of premise 1;
but, at this point, it is not evident whether Descartes’ “clear and distinct”
perception guarantees the truth of anything.
However, in the Fourth Meditation, Descartes goes to great lengths to
guarantee the truth of whatever is clearly and distinctly understood. This
veridical guarantee is based on the theses that God exists and that he cannot
be a deceiver. These arguments, though very interesting, are numerous and
complex, and so they will not be discussed here. Suffice it to say that since
Descartes believes he has established God’s inability to deceive with absolute,
geometrical certainty, he would have to consider anything contradicting this
conclusion to be false. Moreover, Descartes claims that he cannot help but
believe clear and distinct ideas to be true. However, if God put a clear and
distinct idea in him that was false, then he could not help but believe a
falsehood to be true and, to make matters worse, he would never be able to
discover the mistake. Since God would be the author of this false clear and
distinct idea, he would be the source of the error and would, therefore, be a
deceiver, which must be false. Hence, all clear and distinct ideas must be
true, because it is impossible for them to be false given God’s non-deceiving
nature.
That said, the clarity and distinctness of Descartes’ understanding of
mind and body guarantees the truth of premise 1. Hence, both “clear and
distinct” premises are not blunt, unjustified assertions of what he believes
but have very strong rational support from within Descartes’ system. However,
if it turns out that God does not exist or that he can be a deceiver, then all
bets are off. There would then no longer be any veridical guarantee of what is
clearly and distinctly understood and, as a result, the first premise could be
false. Consequently, premise 1 would not bar the possibility of minds requiring
brains to exist and, therefore, this premise would not be absolutely certain as
Descartes supposed. In the end, the conclusion is established with absolute
certainty only when considered from within Descartes’ own epistemological
framework but loses its force if that framework turns out to be false or when
evaluated from outside of it.
These guaranteed truths express some very important points about
Descartes’ conception of mind and body. Notice that mind and body are defined
as complete opposites. This means that the ideas of mind and body represent two
natures that have absolutely nothing in common. And, it is this complete
diversity that establishes the possibility of their independent existence. But,
how can Descartes make a legitimate inference from his independent
understanding of mind and body as completely different things to their
independent existence? To answer this question, recall that every idea of
limited or finite things contains the idea of possible or contingent existence,
and so Descartes is conceiving mind and body as possibly existing all by
themselves without any other creature. Since there is no doubt about this
possibility for Descartes and given the fact that God is all powerful, it
follows that God could bring into existence a mind without a body and vice
versa just as Descartes clearly and distinctly understands them. Hence, the power
of God makes Descartes’ perceived logical possibility of minds existing without
bodies into a metaphysical possibility. As a result, minds without bodies and
bodies without minds would require nothing besides God’s concurrence to exist
and, therefore, they are two really distinct substances.
The Second Version
The argument just examined is formulated in a different way later in the
Sixth Meditation:
“ [T]here is a great difference between the
mind and the body, inasmuch as the body is by its very nature always divisible,
while the mind is utterly indivisible. For when I consider the mind, or myself
in so far as I am merely a thinking thing, I am unable to distinguish any parts
within myself; I understand myself to be something quite single and complete….By
contrast, there is no corporeal or extended thing that I can think of which in
my thought I cannot easily divide into parts; and this very fact makes me
understand that it is divisible. This one argument would be enough to show me
that the mind is completely different from the body…. “(AT VII 86-87: CSM II
59).
This argument can be reformulated as follows, replacing “mind” for “I”
as in the first version:
·
I
understand the mind to be indivisible by its very nature.
·
I
understand body to be divisible by its very nature.
·
Therefore,
the mind is completely different from the body.
Notice the conclusion that mind and body are really distinct is not
explicitly stated but can be inferred from 3. What is interesting about this
formulation is how Descartes reaches his conclusion. He does not assert a clear
and distinct understanding of these two natures as completely different but
instead makes his point based on a particular property of each. However, this
is not just any property but a property each has “by its very nature.”
Something’s nature is just what it is to be that kind of thing, and so the term
“nature” is here being used as synonymous with “essence.” On this account,
extension constitutes the nature or essence of bodily kinds of things; while
thinking constitutes the nature or essence of mental kinds of things. So, here
Descartes is arguing that a property of what it is to be a body, or extended
thing, is to be divisible, while a property of what it is to be a mind or
thinking thing is to be indivisible.
Descartes’ line of reasoning in support of these claims about the
respective natures of mind and body runs as follows. First, it is easy to see
that bodies are divisible. Just take any body, say a pencil or a piece of
paper, and break it or cut it in half. Now you have two bodies instead of one.
Second, based on this line of reasoning, it is easy to see why Descartes
believed his nature or mind to be indivisible: if a mind or an “I” could be
divided, then two minds or “I’s” would result; but since this “I” just is my
self, this would be the same as claiming that the division of my mind results
in two selves, which is absurd. Therefore, the body is essentially divisible
and the mind is essentially indivisible: but how does this lead to the
conclusion that they are completely different?
Here it should be noted that a difference in just any non-essential
property would have only shown that mind and body are not exactly the same. But
this is a much weaker claim than Descartes’ conclusion that they are completely
different. For two things could have the same nature, for example, extension,
but have other, changeable properties or modes distinguishing them. Hence,
these two things would be different in some respect, for example, in shape, but
not completely different, since both would still be extended kinds of things.
Consequently, Descartes needs their complete diversity to claim that he has
completely independent conceptions of each and, in turn, that mind and body can
exist independently of one another.
Descartes can reach this stronger conclusion because these essential
properties are contradictories. On the one hand, Descartes argues that the mind
is indivisible because he cannot perceive himself as having any parts. On the
other hand, the body is divisible because he cannot think of a body except as
having parts. Hence, if mind and body had the same nature, it would be a nature
both with and without parts. Yet such a thing is unintelligible: how could
something both be separable into parts and yet not separable into parts? The
answer is that it can’t, and so mind and body cannot be one and the same but
two completely different natures. Notice that, as with the first version, mind
and body are here being defined as opposites. This implies that divisible body
can be understood without indivisible mind and vice versa. Accordingly each can
be understood as existing all by itself: they are two really distinct
substances.
However, unlike the first version, Descartes does not invoke the
doctrine of clear and distinct ideas to justify his premises. If he had, this
version, like the first, would be absolutely certain from within Descartes’ own
epistemological system. But if removed from this apparatus, it is possible that
Descartes is mistaken about the indivisibility of the mind, because the
possibility of the mind requiring a brain to exist would still be viable. This
would mean that, since extension is part of the nature of mind, it would, being
an extended thing, be composed of parts and, therefore, it would be divisible.
As a result, Descartes could not legitimately reach the conclusion that mind
and body are completely different. This would also mean that the further,
implicit conclusion that mind and body are really distinct could not be reached
either. In the end, the main difficulty with Descartes’ real distinction
argument is that he has not adequately eliminated the possibility of minds
being extended things like brains.
4. The Mind-Body
Problem
The real distinction of mind and body based on their completely diverse
natures is the root of the famous mind-body problem: how can these two
substances with completely different natures causally interact so as to give
rise to a human being capable of having voluntary bodily motions and
sensations? Although several versions of this problem have arisen over the
years, this section will be exclusively devoted to the version of it Descartes
confronted as expressed by Pierre Gassendi, the author of the Fifth Objections,
and Descartes’ correspondent, Princess Elizabeth of Bohemia. Their concern
arises from the claim at the heart of the real distinction argument that mind
and body are completely different or opposite things.
The complete diversity of their respective natures has serious
consequences for the kinds of modes each can possess. For instance, in the
Second Meditation, Descartes argues that he is nothing but a thinking thing or
mind, that is, Descartes argues that he is a “thing that doubts, understands,
affirms, denies, is willing, is unwilling, and also imagines and has sensory
perceptions” (AT VII 28: CSM II 19). It makes no sense to ascribe such modes to
entirely extended, non-thinking things like stones, and therefore, only minds
can have these kinds of modes. Conversely, it makes no sense to ascribe modes of
size, shape, quantity and motion to non-extended, thinking things. For example,
the concept of an unextended shape is unintelligible. Therefore, a mind cannot
be understood to be shaped or in motion, nor can a body understand or sense
anything. Human beings, however, are supposed to be combinations of mind and
body such that the mind’s choices can cause modes of motion in the body, and
motions in certain bodily organs, such as the eye, cause modes of sensation in
the mind.
The mind’s ability to cause motion in the body will be addressed first.
Take for example a voluntary choice, or willing, to raise one’s hand in class
to ask a question. The arm moving upward is the effect while the choice to
raise it is the cause. But willing is a mode of the non-extended mind alone,
whereas the arm’s motion is a mode of the extended body alone: how can the
non-extended mind bring about this extended effect? It is this problem of
voluntary bodily motion or the so-called problem of “mind to body causation”
that so troubled Gassendi and Elizabeth. The crux of their concern was that in
order for one thing to cause motion in another, they must come into contact
with one another as, for example, in the game of pool the cue ball must be in
motion and come into contact with the eight-ball in order for the latter to be
set in motion. The problem is that, in the case of voluntarily bodily
movements, contact between mind and body would be impossible given the mind’s
non-extended nature. This is because contact must be between two surfaces, but
surface is a mode of body, as stated at Principles of Philosophy part II,
section 15. Accordingly, the mind does not have a surface that can come into
contact with the body and cause it to move. So, it seems that if mind and body
are completely different, there is no intelligible explanation of voluntary
bodily movement.
Although Gassendi and Elizabeth limited themselves to the problem of
voluntary bodily movement, a similar problem arises for sensations, or the
so-called problem of “body to mind causation.” For instance, a visual sensation
of a tree is a mode of the mind alone. The cause of this mode would be
explained by the motion of various imperceptible bodies causing parts of the
eye to move, then movements in the optic nerve, which in turn cause various
“animal spirits” to move in the brain and finally result in the sensory idea of
the tree in the mind. But how can the movement of the “animal spirits,” which
were thought to be very fine bodies, bring about the existence of a sensory idea
when the mind is incapable of receiving modes of motion given its non-extended
nature? Again, since the mind is incapable of having motion and a surface, no
intelligible explanation of sensations seems possible either. Therefore, the
completely different natures of mind and body seem to render their causal
interaction impossible.
The consequences of this problem are very serious for Descartes, because
it undermines his claim to have a clear and distinct understanding of the mind
without the body. For humans do have sensations and voluntarily move some of
their bodily limbs and, if Gassendi and Elizabeth are correct, this requires a
surface and contact. Since the mind must have a surface and a capacity for
motion, the mind must also be extended and, therefore, mind and body are not
completely different. This means the “clear and distinct” ideas of mind and
body, as mutually exclusive natures, must be false in order for mind-body
causal interaction to occur. Hence, Descartes has not adequately established that
mind and body are two really distinct substances.
5. Descartes’ Response
to the Mind-Body Problem
Despite the obviousness of this problem, and the amount of attention
given to it, Descartes himself never took this issue very seriously. His
response to Gassendi is a telling example:
“These questions presuppose
amongst other things an explanation of the union between the soul and the body,
which I have not yet dealt with at all. But I will say, for your benefit at
least, that the whole problem contained in such questions arises simply from a
supposition that is false and cannot in any way be proved, namely that, if the
soul and the body are two substances whose nature is different, this prevents
them from being able to act on each other “ (AT VII 213: CSM II 275).
So, Descartes’ response to the mind-body problem is twofold. First,
Descartes contends that a response to this question presupposes an explanation
of the union between the mind (or soul) and the body. Second, Descartes claims
that the question itself stems from the false presupposition that two
substances with completely different natures cannot act on each other. Further
examination of these two points will occur in reverse order.
Descartes’ principles of causation put forward in the Third Meditation
lie at the heart of this second presupposition. The relevant portion of this
discussion is when Descartes argues that the less real cannot cause something
that is more real, because the less real does not have enough reality to bring
about something more real than itself. This principle applies on the general
level of substances and modes. On this account, an infinite substance, that is,
God, is the most real thing because only he requires nothing else in order to
exist; created, finite substances are next most real, because they require only
God’s creative and conservative activity in order to exist; and finally, modes
are the least real, because they require a created substance and an infinite
substance in order to exist. So, on this principle, a mode cannot cause the
existence of a substance since modes are less real than finite substances.
Similarly, a created, finite substance cannot cause the existence of an
infinite substance. But a finite substance can cause the existence of another
finite substance or a mode (since modes are less real than substances). Hence,
Descartes’ point could be that the completely diverse natures of mind and body
do not violate this causal principle, since both are finite substances causing
modes to exist in some other finite substance. This indicates further that the
“activity” of the mind on the body does not require contact and motion, thereby
suggesting that mind and body do not bear a mechanistic causal relation to each
other. More will be said about this below.
The first presupposition concerns an explanation of how the mind is
united with the body. Descartes’ remarks about this issue are scattered across
both his published works and his private correspondence. These texts indicate
that Descartes did not maintain that voluntary bodily movements and sensation
arise because of the causal interaction of mind and body by contact and motion.
Rather, he maintains a version of the form-matter theory of soul-body union
endorsed by some of his scholastic-Aristotelian predecessors and
contemporaries. Although a close analysis of the texts in question cannot be
conducted here, a brief summary of how this theory works for Descartes can be
provided.
Before providing this summary, however, it is important to disclaim that
this scholastic-Aristotelian interpretation is a minority position amongst
Descartes scholars. The traditional view maintains that Descartes’ human being
is composed of two substances that causally interact in a mechanistic fashion.
This traditional view led some of Descartes’ successors, such as Malebranche
and Leibniz (who also believed in the real distinction of mind and body), to
devise metaphysical systems wherein mind and body do not causally interact
despite appearances to the contrary. Other philosophers considered the
mind-body problem to be insurmountable, thereby denying their real distinction:
they claim that everything is either extended (as is common nowadays) or mental
(as George Berkeley argued in the 18th century). Indeed, this traditional,
mechanistic interpretation of Descartes is so deeply ingrained in the minds of
philosophers today, that most do not even bother to argue for it. However, a
notable exception is Marleen Rozemond, who argues for the incompatibility of
Descartes’ metaphysics with any scholastic-Aristotelian version of mind or
soul-body union. Those interested in closely examining her arguments should
consult her book Descartes’s Dualism. A book arguing in favor of the
scholastic-Aristotelian interpretation is entitled Descartes and the
Metaphysics of Human Nature; Chapter 5 specifically addresses Rozemond’s
concerns.
Two major stumbling blocks Rozemond raises for the
scholastic-Aristotelian interpretation concern the mind’s status as a
substantial form and the extent to which Descartes can maintain a form of the
human body. However, recall that Descartes rejects substantial forms because of
their final causal component. Descartes’ argument was based on the fact (as he
understood it) that the scholastics were ascribing mental properties to
entirely non-mental things like stones. Since the mind is an entirely mental
thing, these arguments just do not apply to it. Hence, Descartes’ particular
rejection of substantial forms does not necessarily imply that Descartes did
not view the mind as a substantial form. Indeed, as Paul Hoffman noted:
Descartes really rejects the attempt to use the human soul as a model
for explanations in the entirely physical world. This makes it possible that
Descartes considered the human mind to be the only substantial form. At first
glance this may seem ad hoc but it is also important to notice that rejecting
the existence of substantial forms with the exception of the mind or rational
soul was not uncommon amongst Descartes’ contemporaries.
Although the mind’s status as a substantial form may seem at risk
because of its meager explicit textual support, Descartes suggests that the
mind a “substantial form” twice in a draft of open letter to his enemy Voetius:
“Yet, if the soul is
recognized as merely a substantial form, while other such forms consist in the
configuration and motion of parts, this very privileged status it has compared
with other forms shows that its nature is quite different from theirs” (AT III
503: CSMK 207-208).
Descartes then remarks “this is confirmed by the example of the soul,
which is the true substantial form of man” (AT III 508: CSMK 208). Although
other passages do not make this claim explicitly, they do imply (in some sense)
that the mind is a substantial form. For instance, Descartes claims in a letter
to Mesland dated 9 February 1645, that the soul is “substantially united” with
the human body (AT IV 166: CSMK 243). This “substantial union” was a technical
term amongst the scholastics denoting the union between a substantial form and
matter to form a complete substance. Consequently, there is some reason for
believing that the human mind is the only substantial form left standing in
Descartes’ metaphysics.
Another major stumbling block recognized by Rozemond is the extent to
which, if any, Descartes’ metaphysics can maintain a principle for organizing
extension into a human body. This was a point of some controversy amongst the
scholastics themselves. Philosophers maintaining a Thomistic position argued
that the human soul is the human body’s principle of organization. While
others, maintaining a basically Scotistic position, argued that some other form
besides the human soul is the form of the body. This “form of corporeity”
organizes matter for the sake of being a human body but does not result in a
full-fledged human being. Rather it makes a body with the potential for union
with the human soul. The soul then actualizes this potential resulting in a complete
human being. If Descartes did hold a fundamentally scholastic theory of
mind-body union, then is it more Thomistic or Scotistic? Since intellect and
will are the only faculties of the mind, it does not have the faculty for
organizing matter for being a human body. So, if Descartes’ theory is
scholastic, it must be most in line with some version of the Scotistic theory.
Rozemond argues that Descartes’ rejection of all other substantial forms
(except the human mind or soul) precludes this kind of theory since he cannot
appeal to the doctrine of substantial forms like the Scotists.
Although Descartes argues that bodies, in the general sense, are
constituted by extension, he also maintains that species of bodies are
determined by the configuration and motion of their parts. This doctrine of
“configuration and motion of parts” serves the same purpose as the doctrine of
substantial forms with regards to entirely physical things. But the main
difference between the two is that Descartes’ doctrine does not employ final
causes. Recall that substantial forms organize matter for the purpose of being
a species of thing. The purpose of a human body endowed with only the form of
corporeity is union with the soul. Hence, the organization of matter into a
human body is an effect that is explained by the final cause or purpose of
being disposed for union. But, on Descartes’ account, the explanatory order
would be reversed: a human body’s disposition for union is an effect resulting
from the configuration and motion of parts. So, even though Descartes does not
have recourse to substantial forms, he still has recourse to the configuration
of matter and to the dispositions to which it gives rise, including “all the
dispositions required to preserve that union” (AT IV 166: CSMK 243). Hence, on
this account, Descartes gets what he needs, namely, Descartes gets a body
properly configured for potential union with the mind, but without recourse to
the scholastic notion of substantial forms with their final causal component.
Another feature of this basically Scotistic position is that the soul
and the body were considered incomplete substances themselves, while their
union results in one, complete substance. Surely Descartes maintains that mind
and body are two substances but in what sense, if any, can they be considered
incomplete? Descartes answers this question in the Fourth Replies. He argues
that a substance may be complete insofar as it is a substance but incomplete
insofar as it is referred to some other substance together with which it forms
yet some third substance. This can be applied to mind and body as follows: the
mind insofar as it is a thinking thing is a complete substance, while the body
insofar as it is an extended thing is a complete substance, but each taken individually
is only an incomplete human being.
This account is repeated in the following excerpt from a letter to
Regius dated December 1641:
“For there you said that the
body and the soul, in relation to the whole human being, are incomplete substances;
and it follows from their being incomplete that what they constitute is a being
through itself” (that is, an ens per se; AT III 460: CSMK 200).
The technical sense of the term “being through itself” was intended to
capture the fact that human beings do not require any other creature but only
God’s concurrence to exist. Accordingly, a being through itself, or ens per se,
is a substance. Also notice that the claim in the letter to Regius that two
incomplete substances together constitute a being through itself is reminiscent
of Descartes’ remarks in the Fourth Replies. This affinity between the two
texts indicates that the union of mind and body results in one complete
substance or being through itself. This just means that mind and body are the metaphysical
parts (mind and body are incomplete substances in this respect) that constitute
one, whole human being, which is a complete substance in its own right. Hence,
a human being is not the result of two substances causally interacting by means
of contact and motion, as Gassendi and Elizabeth supposed, but rather they bear
a relation of act and potency that results in one, whole and complete
substantial human being.
This sheds some light on why Descartes thought that an account of
mind-body union would put Gassendi’s and Elizabeth’s concerns to rest: they
misconceived the union of mind and body as a mechanical relation when in fact
it is a relation of act and potency. This avoids Gassendi’s and Elizabeth’s
version of this problem. This aversion is accomplished by the fact that modes
of voluntary motion (and sensations, by extrapolation) should be ascribed to a
whole human being and not to the mind or the body taken individually. This is
made apparent in a 21 May 1643 letter to Elizabeth where Descartes
distinguishes between various “primitive notions.” The most general are the
notions of being, number, duration, and so on, which apply to all conceivable
things. He then goes on to distinguish the notions of mind and body:
“Then, as regards body in particular,
we have only the notion of extension, which entails the notions of shape and
motion; and as regards the soul on its own, we have only the notion of thought,
which includes the perceptions of the intellect and the inclinations of the
will”(AT III 665: CSMK 218).
Here body and soul (or mind) are primitive notions and the notions of
their respective modes are the notions “entailed by” or “included in” these
primitives. Descartes then discusses the primitive notion of mind-body union:
Lastly, as regards the soul
and the body together, we have only the notion of their union, on which depends
our notion of the soul’s power to move the body, and the body’s power to act on
the soul and cause its sensations and passions (AT III 665: CSMK 218).
In light of the immediately preceding lines, this indicates that
voluntary bodily movements and sensations are not modes of the body alone, or
the mind alone, but rather are modes of “the soul and the body together.” This
is at least partially confirmed in the following lines from Principles, part I,
article 48:
“But we also experience within
ourselves certain other things, which must not be referred either to the mind
alone or to the body alone. These arises, as will be made clear in the appropriate
place, from the close and intimate union of our mind with the body. This list
includes, first, appetites like hunger and thirds; secondly, the emotions or
passions” . . . (AT VIIIA 23: CSM I 209).
These texts indicate that the mind or soul is united with the body so as
to give rise to another whole complete substance composed of these two
metaphysical parts. And, moreover, this composite substance now has the
capacity for having modes of its own, namely, modes of voluntary bodily
movement and sensation, which neither the mind nor the body can have
individually. So, voluntary bodily movements are not modes of the body alone
caused by the mind, nor are sensations modes of the mind alone caused by the
body. Rather, both are modes of a whole and complete human being. On this
account, it makes no sense to ask how the non-extended mind can come into
contact with the body to cause these modes. To ask this would be to get off on
the wrong foot entirely, since contact between these two completely diverse substances
is not required for these modes to exist. Rather all that is necessary is for
the mind to actualize the potential in a properly disposed human body to form
one, whole, human being to whom is attributed modes of voluntary movement and
sensation.
Although the scholastic-Aristotelian interpretation avoids the
traditional causal interaction problem based on the requirements of contact and
motion, it does run up against another version of that problem, namely, a
problem of formal causation. This is a problem facing any
scholastic-Aristotelian theory of mind or soul-body union where the soul is
understood to be an immaterial substantial form. Recall that the immaterial
mind or soul as substantial form is suppose to act on a properly disposed human
body in order to result in a full-fledged human being. The problem of formal
causal interaction is: how can an immaterial soul assubstantial form act on the
potential in a material thing? Can any sense be made of the claim that a
non-extended or immaterial things acts on anything? Descartes noticed in a
letter to Regius (AT III 493: CSMK 206) that the scholastics did not try to
answer this question and so he and Regius need not either. The likely
explanation of their silence is that the act-potency relation was considered
absolutely fundamental to scholastic-Aristotelian philosophy and, therefore, it
required no further explanation. So, in the end, even if Descartes’ theory is
as described here, it does not evade all the causal problems associated with
uniting immaterial souls or mind to their respective bodies. , However, if this
proposed account is true, it helps to cast Descartes’ philosophy in a new light
and to redirect the attention of scholars to the formal causal problems
involved.
No comments:
Post a Comment