Overall Analysis and Themes
The prominent place the Symposium holds in our canon comes as much as a
result of its literary merit as its philosophical merit. While other works
among Plato's middle-period dialogues, such as the Republic and the Phaedo,
contain more philosophical meat, more closely examining the Theory of Forms and
intensely cross-examining interlocutors, none can match the dramatic force of
the Symposium. It is lively and entertaining, with sharp and witty
characterization that gives us valuable insight into the social life of
Athenian intellectual circles.
From a philosophical standpoint, the Symposium is also far from
bankrupt. Not only does it give us some insight into the Theory of Forms in
Diotima's discussion of the Form of Beauty, but it also gives us a number of
varying perspectives on love. Significantly, we see Plato rejecting the romanticization
of sexual love, valuing above all an asexual and all-consuming passion for
wisdom and beauty. Ultimately, he concludes, the philosopher's search for
wisdom is the most valuable of all pursuits. In the Symposium, Plato values
philosophy, as exemplified by Socrates, over a number of other arts which are
given as points of comparison: medicine, as exemplified by Eryximachus, comedy
as exemplified by Aristophanes, and tragedy as exemplified by Agathon.
The series of speeches in praise of Love are not simply meant as beating
around the bush that leads up to the main event. They mirror Diotima's
discussion of the mysteries, where she suggests that one can approach the truth
only through a slow and careful ascent. Similarly, we can see each speech, with
a few exceptions, as coming closer and closer to the truth. This suggestion is
reinforced by the fact that Socrates alludes to all the foregoing speeches in
his own speech, as if to suggest that his words could not be spoken until
everyone else had said their piece. This staggered approach to truth is also
reflected in the framing of the narrative, whereby we are only able to gain
access to this story through a series of narrative filters.
We should note that Socrates is the exemplar of the lover of wisdom and
the lover of beauty, but is neither wise nor beautiful himself. In this way, he
best represents Love, which Diotima describes as a mediating spirit that moves
between gods and men. Love himself never has anything, but is always desirous
of happiness, beauty, and wisdom. The same is true with Socrates. Those who
follow his lead will not necessarily attain wisdom, but will find fulfillment
in a life-long pursuit of wisdom. The state of having attained wisdom is
represented by Diotima, not Socrates, and she speaks through Socrates as a
god-like and unapproachable figure.
There is also some discussion as to exactly what is being discussed in
the Symposium. The Greek word eros leaves the matter ambiguous as to whether we
are discussing love in the normal, human, sense of the word, or if we are
discussing desire in a much broader sense. The later speeches in particular
tend toward this broader interpretation. Diotima gives what is perhaps a
satisfactory answer by suggesting that, while all kinds of desire might be
considered love, we normally restrict use of that term to one particular kind
of desire, the desire that exists between two human beings.
Philosophy aside, however, the Symposium still makes a terrific read.
Aristophanes' myth is delightful, Alcibiades' drunken antics are entertaining,
and the whole narrative shimmers with life. We also get a very clear sense of
the dynamics of sexual attraction and courtship--both male-male and
male-female--in ancient Athens, and we are given a beautiful portrait of one of
the high-points of the Athenian scene: the symposium.
N.B.: There are no natural breaks in the text as Plato wrote it, so
these notes on the text have been divided artificially, sections beginning or
breaking off where a new theme or topic is introduced or dropped. Because page
numbers may vary from edition to edition, these sections have been demarcated
according to the Stephanus numbers, the page numbers from the 1578 complete
works edited by Henri Estienne ("Stephanus" in Latin). The Stephanus numbers
are the standard page references in scholarly work on Plato, and most editions
of his work contain the Stephanus numbers along the margins.
Summary
The dialogue opens with Apollodorus agreeing to tell an unnamed
companion who is a rich businessman the famous story of the party held in honor
of Agathon to celebrate the success of his first tragedy. Apollodorus retells
the account he gave to Glaucon (Plato's half-brother and main interlocutor of
the Republic) who had in turn heard of the party from some other, less reliable
source. Glaucon had thought Apollodorus had been in attendance, but Apollodorus
points out that the party took place many years ago, when he and Glaucon were
just children. Apollodorus had heard the story from Aristodemus, one of the
guests at the party, and had also checked some of the facts with Socrates
himself.
The story begins with Aristodemus encountering Socrates, who has
recently bathed and put on sandals--things he rarely does. Aristodemus inquires
as to why Socrates is all dressed up, and Socrates answers that he is going to
dinner at Agathon's. Agathon's tragedy won him first prize at the Lenaean
festival the previous day, and while Socrates shunned the large crowds of
yesterday's celebrations, he promised to join Agathon today. Socrates invites
Aristodemus to join him, and while Aristodemus is at first hesitant about
dropping in uninvited, Socrates persuades him that he must come.
Aristodemus and Socrates head off toward Agathon's together, but
Socrates keeps falling behind, lost in thought. Socrates urges Aristodemus to
go ahead, saying he will catch up. As a result, Aristodemus arrives at
Agathon's without Socrates and is welcomed in alone. Agathon is delighted to
see him, saying that he was looking for him yesterday so as to invite him.
Aristodemus explains that he came upon Socrates' invitation, and is surprised
to find that Socrates has not caught up with him. Agathon sends out a slave to
find him, and the slave returns, reporting that Socrates is standing on a neighbor's
porch and will not come in. Agathon orders the slave to go and fetch him in,
but Aristodemus insists that Socrates be left alone: he will come of his own
accord when he has finished thinking.
Aristodemus joins the other guests and they begin eating. Among those
assembled, there is the young Phaedrus, Agathon's life-partner Pausanias, a
doctor named Eryximachus, and the great comic playwright Aristophanes. The meal
is halfway over by the time Socrates finally appears. Agathon encourages
Socrates to join him on his couch so that he may share in the wisdom that came
to Socrates on the neighboring porch. Socrates remarks that if wisdom could
flow freely from the wiser to the less wise, Socrates should be the one
benefiting from sitting near Agathon. Noting the mocking tone in Socrates'
voice, Agathon suggests they might test one another's wisdom later that
evening.
After dinner, Pausanias takes responsibility for organizing the
drinking. All the guests but Socrates have participated in the wild revelry of the
previous night and are feeling rather hung over. Eryximachus recommends that
they not drink too much this evening in the interests of their health. He
suggests further that they send away the flute-girl, who was to be their
entertainment, and engage instead in conversation. He had been speaking
recently to Phaedrus, who had lamented that the poets compose songs of praise
to all the gods but Love. Consequently, Eryximachus recommends that each person
present, starting with Phaedrus, make the finest speech he can in praise of
Love.
Commentary
The "symposium," translated literally as
"drinks-party," was a central and highly ritualized part of Greek
social practice. The party takes place in a square room, the andron, which is
the main room in the men's part of the house. Guests at the symposium, who are
always freeborn adult males, recline on couches, two to a couch, arranged in a
square that allows easy conversation. The party is sharply divided into two
parts. First, there is the meal, which is not a particularly ritualized affair.
Once the meal is done, the drinking begins. First, the guests are cleaned and
perfumed by attendant slaves, and then unmixed wine is poured out and tasted,
while the guests sing hymns in honor of the gods. One member of the party--Pausanias
in this case--is appointed "symposiarch," and determines in
consultation with the other guests exactly how much wine will be drunk and to
what extent the wine should be mixed with water. Normally, the subsequent
drinking is accompanied by conversation, singing, and speeches. Male and female
slaves provide music and other entertainment, and serve as "escorts,"
flirting with, though rarely having sex with, the guests. That Eryximachus
sends away the flute-player suggests that this party will be more serious than
normal, and philosophical discussion will take the place of erotic stimulation.
The Symposium is framed by several levels of narrative distancing.
Apollodorus tells the story to his companion, but the story he tells is
actually a retelling of the story he told Glaucon. This story has in turn been
gleaned from Aristodemus, and confirmed by Socrates. Glaucon also notes that he
has heard a version of the story. Plato, the actual writer of the dialogue, is
nowhere found in this cast of characters, so there must be a further level of
retelling by which Plato himself learns the story. All this framing serves two
immediate purposes. One is to suggest the extreme importance of this dialogue.
It is being discussed years after the fact, there are many versions floating
about, and everyone wants to hear the story told. The other purpose is to
distance the narration from the events themselves, suggesting that Plato's
dialogue is not a direct transcription of factual events so much as an
imaginative retelling that is probably more fiction than fact. The characters
in the dialogue are celebrating a victory for the dramatist, Agathon, and the
dialogue itself is a drama, though it treats of philosophy rather than tragedy.
This framing also reflects another theme of the dialogue, which is the
difficulty of attaining the truth. There are several layers of narrative, and
in the story itself we get several different speeches. In both cases, we are
given the sense that truth is not something we can be given, but something that
must be sifted through, something we must work to acquire.
Agathon's victory comes at the Lenaean festival, one of the dramatic
festivals that were so central in Ancient Greek society. Tragedians such as
Aeschyllus, Sophocles, and Euripides competed in these festivals presented in
honor of Dionysus, the god of wine, fertility, and ritual dance, and patron of
drama and poetry (Plato, too, wrote some plays, though none of them survive).
The winner of the festival became a major celebrity, and was widely celebrated.
Plato was generally skeptical about poetry, and we find expression of
this mistrust in Socrates' sarcastic remark to Agathon about his great wisdom.
Tragedy purports to lay wisdom upon great crowds of people directly and
immediately. As this dialogue and its framing devices suggest, Plato is of a
mind that wisdom is something that must be worked toward, not something that
can be given easily. Socrates suggests that wisdom is not something one can
gain by osmosis, simply by sitting near someone wiser than oneself. Implicit in
this suggestion is the claim that tragedy does not transmit wisdom, and that
only careful philosophical thinking can be a successful teacher.
We find further evidence of this claim in Socrates' delay in arriving at
the party. He gets lost in thought and must stand still where he is and think
until he has worked his way through a problem. This kind of inner dialectic is
clearly common with Socrates, as Aristodemus is already familiar with it. We
might liken Socrates' behavior with that of the stereotypical
"absent-minded professor" who cannot deal with day-to-day activities
as a result of being so caught up in intellectual pursuits. Socrates does not
feel compelled to abide by social norms, valuing philosophy over propriety.
No comments:
Post a Comment