Epistemology is the study of the nature, source, limits, and validity of
knowledge. It is especially interested in developing criteria for evaluating
claims people make that they "know" something. In particular, it
considers questions such as: What is knowledge? What is the difference between
knowledge and belief? If you know something, does that mean that you are
certain about it? Is knowledge really possible?
Traditionally, philosophers have thought that if someone knows X, that
means that he or she (1) believes that X is true, (2) X is, in fact, true, and
(3) the person who claims to know X can give a justification or rationale for
thinking that X is true. Such a justification can be given by appealing to
intuition (immediate, personal certainty that X is true), reasoning (proving
that X is true based on shared strategies of argumentation), or sense
experience (public, repeatable, verifiable demonstration or experiment showing
that X is true).
Despite the fact that intuition is a common phenomenon, philosophers
have often been hesitant to identify it as a form of knowledge--primarily
because there seems to be little way to determine whether it does, in fact,
provide knowledge as opposed simply to lucky guesses. So most philosophers
focus, instead, on reason and sense experience as the bases of knowledge. These
two latter ways of approaching the question of knowledge are identified as
rationalism and empiricism.
A rationalist epistemology claims that knowledge (as opposed to opinion)
is possible only if it is based on self-evident and absolutely certain
principles. Such principles are not learned through experience; instead, they
are implicit in the very notion of reasoning (in Latin: ratio) itself. Sense
experience cannot provide the certainty needed to guarantee that what we claim
to know is true. So, like mathematicians, we have to rely on reason itself as
the basis for determining whether our opinions are justified true beliefs (that
is, knowledge).
Plato is an example of a rationalist. He says that sense experience
fails to provide us with any guarantee that what we experience is, in fact,
true. The information we get by relying on sense experience is constantly
changing and is often unreliable. It can be corrected and evaluated for
dependability only be appealing to principles that themselves do not change.
These unchanging principles (or "Forms") are the bases of what it
means to think or reason in the first place. So if someone can show that an
opinion or belief he or she has is based on these undoubtable principles of
thought, he or she has a firm foundation for the opinion. That foundation is
what allows us to think of a belief as more than simply opinion; it is what
allows us to identify the belief as justified and true, and that is what is
meant by knowledge.
Knowledge for the rationalist is thus what can be deduced from
principles that cannot be otherwise; they are undoubtable
("indubitable"). Examples of such principles include: "Bachelors
are unmarried males," "A thing cannot be and not be at the same time
in the same way," "Triangles have three sides," and "A
whole is always greater than any one of its parts." These statements are
known with certainty to be true because the very meaning of the terms involved
(e.g., bachelors, triangles, things, wholes) requires that we think of them in
certain ways (without relying on sense experience). We thus know about some
things prior to any sense experience we have or could have. Such knowledge is
called a priori. Any knowledge that relies on (that is, comes after or is
posterior to) sense experience is called a posteriori.
Rene' Descartes (1596-1650) is another example of a rationalist. Instead
of beginning philosophical inquiry (like the Milesians) with the study of the
nature of reality, he suggests that we ask what it would mean to know about
reality. To believe that reality is fundamentally water or the Indeterminate or
whatever seems pointless, he claims, unless we know first whether our belief
itself is justified. To determine whether our beliefs are justified, we have to
be able to trace them back to a statement, belief, or proposition that cannot
be doubted. Such a proposition could provide the firm foundation on which all
subsequent beliefs could be grounded; it would guarantee that all subsequent
claims based on it would be true.
In order to identify an ultimate principle of truth on which all other
knowledge can be based, Descartes develops a method that suspends our
confidence in what we have been taught, what our senses tell us, what we
"think" is obvious--in short, in regard to everything we know. In
order to determine whether there is anything we can know with certainty, he
says that we first have to doubt everything we know. Such a radical doubt might
not seem reasonable, and Descartes certainly does not mean that we really
should doubt everything. What he suggests is that, in order to see if there is
some belief that cannot be doubted, we should temporarily pretend that
everything we know is questionable.
Since sense experience is sometimes deceiving, it is obvious to
Descartes that a posteriori claims (e.g., that this milk tastes sour or that
suit is dark blue) cannot be the basis for claims of knowledge. We do not know
that what we experience through our senses is true; at least, we are not
certain of it. So the best thing to do is to doubt our senses. Likewise, we
cannot be sure that we really have bodies or that our experience of the world
in general can be trusted; after all, we might be dreaming the whole thing.
Next, we cannot even be sure that mathematical propositions such as 2+3=5 or
that triangles always have three sides are true because some evil power might
be deceiving us to think such things, when it is possible that even
propositions that seem evident to us as true might themselves be really false.
But even if an evil genie deceives us about all other beliefs, there is one
belief that we cannot be mistaken about, and that is that we are thinking. Even
to doubt this is to affirm it. Thinking proves that we exist (at least as minds
or thinking things, regardless of whether we have bodies). The body is not an
essential part of the self because we can doubt its existence in a way that we
cannot doubt the existence of the mind.
So Descartes concludes that I know one thing clearly and distinctly,
namely, that I exist because I think: "Cogito ergo sum," I think,
therefore I exist. From this starting point I can begin to note other truths
that I know clearly and distinctly, such as the principle of identity (A is A)
and the notion that things in the world are "substances." Since
identity and substance are ideas that are not based on sensation, they must be
innate (that is, they must be implicit in the very act of thinking itself).
Even sensible things (e.g., a block of wax) are knowable not based on sense
experience but intellectually, insofar as we know them to be the same things
even though their sensible appearances might change dramatically.
In order to be certain that we are not deceived when we claim to know
something, Descartes must dispose of the evil genie. This is done by proving
that an all-good, all-powerful God would not permit us to be deceived. If there
is such a God, we can have knowledge. Since the senses cannot be trusted to
provide a proof that God exists, only a proof based on the principle of the
cogito ("I think, therefore I am") will work. That proof can be
summarized in the following way:
I know I exist; but the "I" who exists is obviously imperfect;
otherwise I would not have doubts about what I know in the first place. To know
that I, an imperfect thing, exist means that I already know that a perfect
thing must exist in terms of which my own existence is meaningful. I know what
it means to be imperfect only if I already know what perfection is. But I do
not know perfection in virtue of my self; therefore there must be a perfect
substance (God) who exists in terms of which my own imperfect existence is
intelligible. No perfect (all-good, all-powerful) being would deceive us into
thinking that we know something with certainty when, in fact, we are mistaken
about it. So if there is a God, then no evil genie could exist who tricks us
regarding clear and distinct knowledge (such as mathematical reasoning).
We have a "great inclination" to believe that there are
physical objects that are external to the mind. But since only those objects
known in terms of mathematical properties--not those imagined by use of the
senses--can be known clearly and distinctly, the only knowledge we can have of
such objects is in terms of mathematical, quantifiable physics. The only real
knowledge we can have, then, is of things understood as functions of laws of
physics. The objects we see are not the objects we know, because what we know
is intelligible only in terms of the clarity and precision of the formulae of
physics. Information provided by the senses cannot therefore be the basis of
knowledge.
Certitude is thus grounded in the knowledge of the self, which is itself
intelligible only if there is a God who guarantees that we are not deceived
about what we know of the world clearly and distinctly (i.e., mathematically).
By appeal to reason alone, we are able to know: this is the main message of
rationalism.
Objections to Rationalism:
1. There is no agreement among
philosophers or cultures about so-called self-evident ideas. Supposedly
self-evident ideas have often been rejected at later times in history.
2. Self-evident ideas provide
no knowledge about the world. Though sense experience may not be certain, it
provides us with information which is as reliable as we need. The fact that a
belief is not absolutely certain should not disqualify it for knowledge. Why
not say that something is known as long as there is no good reason to doubt it?
Of course, that might mean that occasionally we would have to admit that what
we thought we knew was something that we really didn't know. So what?
No comments:
Post a Comment