In many of his dialogues, Plato
mentions supra-sensible entities he calls "Forms" (or
"Ideas"). So, for example, in the Phaedo, we are told that particular sensible equal
things—for example, equal sticks or stones (see Phaedo 74a-75d)—are equal
because of their "participation" or "sharing" in the
character of the Form of Equality, which is absolutely, changelessly,
perfectly, and essentially equal. Plato sometimes characterizes this
participation in the Form as a kind of imaging, or approximation of the Form.
The same may be said of the many things that are greater or smaller and the
Forms of Great and Small (Phaedo 75c-d), or the many tall things and the Form
of Tall (Phaedo 100e), or the many beautiful things and the Form of Beauty
(Phaedo 75c-d, Symposium 211e, Republic
V.476c). When Plato writes about instances of Forms "approximating"
Forms, it is easy to infer that, for Plato, Forms are exemplars. If so, Plato
believes that The Form of Beauty is perfect beauty, the Form of Justice is
perfect justice, and so forth. Conceiving of Forms in this way was important to
Plato because it enabled the philosopher who grasps the entities to be best
able to judge to what extent sensible instances of the Forms are good examples
of the Forms they approximate.
Scholars disagree about the scope of
what is often called "the theory of Forms," and question whether
Plato began holding that there are only Forms for a small range of properties,
such as tallness, equality, justice, beauty, and so on, and then widened the
scope to include Forms corresponding to every term that can be applied to a
multiplicity of instances. In the Republic, he writes as if there may be a
great multiplicity of Forms—for example, in Book X of that work, we find him
writing about the Form of Bed (see Republic X.596b). He may have come to
believe that for any set of things that shares some property, there is a Form
that gives unity to the set of things (and univocity to the term by which we
refer to members of that set of things). Knowledge involves the recognition of
the Forms (Republic V.475e-480a), and any reliable application of this
knowledge will involve the ability compare the particular sensible
instantiations of a property to the Form.
Immortality and Reincarnation
In the early transitional dialogue,
the Meno, Plato has Socrates introduce
the Orphic and Pythagorean idea that souls are immortal and existed before our
births. All knowledge, he explains, is actually recollected from this prior
existence. In perhaps the most famous passage in this dialogue, Socrates
elicits recollection about geometry from one of Meno's slaves (Meno 81a-86b). Socrates' apparent interest in, and
fairly sophisticated knowledge of, mathematics appears wholly new in this
dialogue. It is an interest, however, that shows up plainly in the middle
period dialogues, especially in the middle books of the Republic.
Several arguments for the immortality
of the soul, and the idea that souls are reincarnated into different life
forms, are also featured in Plato's Phaedo (which also includes the famous
scene in which Socrates drinks the hemlock and utters his last words).
Stylometry has tended to count the Phaedo among the early dialogues, whereas
analysis of philosophical content has tended to place it at the beginning of
the middle period. Similar accounts of the transmigration of souls may be
found, with somewhat different details, in Book X of the Republic and in the
Phaedrus, as well as in several
dialogues of the late period, including the Timaeus and the Laws. No traces of the doctrine of recollection, or
the theory of reincarnation or transmigration of souls, are to be found in the
dialogues we listed above as those of the early period.
Metaxy
Metaxy (Greek: μεταξύ) or metaxu is
defined in Plato's Symposium via the character of the priestess Diotima as the
"in-between" or "middle ground". Diotima, tutoring
Socrates, uses the term to show how oral tradition can be perceived by
different people in different ways. In the poem by Socrates she depicts Eros as
not an extreme or purity; rather, as a daimon Eros is in-between the divine
Gods and mankind. Diotima thus exposes the flaws of oral tradition; it uses
strong contrasts to express truth, thus revealing vulnerability to sophistry.
This portion of the dialogue points to the idea that reality is perceptible
only through one's character (which includes one's desires and prejudices and
one's limited understanding of logic). Man moves through the world of Becoming,
the ever changing world of sensory perception, into the world of Being—the
world of forms, absolutes and transcendence, by Metaxy. Man transcends his
place in Becoming by Eros, where man reaches the Highest Good, an intuitive and
mystical state of consciousness. Neoplatonists like Plotinus later used the
concept to express an ontological placement of Man between the Gods and
animals. Much like Diotima did in expressing that Eros as daemon was in-between
the Gods and mankind. Love (Ἔρως Eros) as the thing in between or child of
Poverty (Πενία Penia) and Possession (Πόρος Poros)
No comments:
Post a Comment