The term “contemporary phenomenology” refers
to a wide area of 20th and 21st century philosophy in which the study of the
structures of consciousness occupies center stage. Since the appearance of
Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason and subsequent developments in phenomenology and
hermeneutics after Husserl, it has no longer been possible to view
consciousness as a simple scientific object of study. It is, in fact, the
precondition for any sort of meaningful experience, even the simple
apprehension of objects in the world. While the basic features of
phenomenological consciousness – intentionality, self-awareness, embodiment,
and so forth—have been the focus of analysis, Continental philosophers such as
Paul Ricoeur and Jacques Derrida go further in adding a linguistically creative
dimension. They argue that metaphor and symbol act as the primary interpreters
of reality, generating richer layers of perception, expression, and meaning in
speculative thought. The interplay of metaphor and phenomenology introduces serious
challenges and ambiguities within long-standing assumptions in the history of
Western philosophy, largely with respect to the strict divide between the
literal and figurative modes of reality based in the correspondence theory of
truth. Since the end of the 20th century, the role of metaphor in the
production of cognitive structures has been taken up and extended in new
productive directions, including “naturalized phenomenology” and
straightforward cognitive science, notably in the work of G. Lakoff and M.
Johnson, M. Turner, D. Zahavi, and S. Gallagher.
1.
Overview
This article highlights the
definitive points in the ongoing philosophical conversation about metaphorical
language and it’s centrality in phenomenology. The phenomenological
interpretation of metaphor, at times presented as a critique, is a radical
alternative to the conventional analysis of metaphor. The conventional view,
largely inherited from Aristotle, is also known as the “substitution model.” In
the traditional, or standard approach, the uses and applications of metaphor
have been restricted to (along with other related symbolic phenomena/tropes)
the realms of rhetoric and poetics. In this view, metaphor is none other than a
kind of categorical mistake, a deviance of sense produced in order to create a
lively effect.
While somewhat contested,
the standard substitution theory, also referred to as the “similarity theory,”
generally defines metaphor as a stylistic literary device involving a deviant
and dyadic movement which shifts meaning from one word to another. This view,
first and most thoroughly articulated by Aristotle, reinforces the epistemic
primacy of the literal, where metaphor can only operate as a secondary device,
one which is dependent on the prior level of ordinary descriptive language,
where the first-order language in itself contains nothing metaphorical. In most
cases, the relation between two orders, literal and figurative, has been
interpreted as an implicit simile, which expresses a “this is that” structure.
For example, Aristotle mentions, in Poetics:
When the poet says of
Achilles that he “Leapt on the foe as a lion,” this is a simile; when he says
of him, “the lion leapt” it is a metaphor—here, since both are courageous,
[Homer] has transferred to Achilles the name of “lion.” (1406b 20-3)
In purely conventional
terms, poetic language can only be said to refer to itself; that is, it can
accomplish imaginative description through metaphorical attribution, but the
description does not refer to any reality outside of itself. For the purposes
of traditional rhetoric and poetics in the Aristotelian mode, metaphor may
serve many purposes; it can be clever, creative, or eloquent, but never true in
terms of referring to new propositional content. This is due to the restriction
of comparison to substitution, such that the cognitive impact of the metaphoric
transfer of meaning is produced by assuming similarities between literal and
figurative domains of objects and the descriptive predicates attributed to
them.
The phenomenological
interpretation of metaphor, however, not only challenges the substitution
model, it advances the role of metaphor far beyond the limits of traditional
rhetoric. In the Continental philosophical tradition, the most extensive
developments of metaphor’s place in phenomenology are found in the work of
Martin Heidegger, Paul Ricoeur and Jacques Derrida. They all, in slightly
different ways, see figurative language as the primary vehicle for the
disclosure and creation of new forms of meaning which emerge from an
ontological, rather than purely epistemic or objectifying engagement with the
world.
a.
The Conventional View: Aristotle’s Contribution to Substitution Model
Metaphor consists in giving
the thing a name that belongs to something else; the transference being either
from species to genus, or from genus to species, or from species to species, on
the grounds of analogy. (Poetics 1457b 6-9)
While his philosophical predecessor Plato
condemns the use of figurative speech for its role in rhetorike, “the art of
persuasion,” Aristotle recognizes its stylistic merits and provides us with the
first systematic analysis of metaphor and its place in literature and the
mimetic arts. His briefer descriptions of how metaphors are to be used can be
found in Rhetoric and Poetics, while his extended analysis of how metaphor
operates within the context of language as a whole can be inferred by reading
On Interpretation together with Metaphysics. The descriptive use of metaphor
can be understood as an extension of its meaning; the term derives from the
Greek metaphora, from metaphero, meaning “to transfer or carry over.” Thus, the
figurative trope emerges from a movement of substitution, involving the
transference of a word to a new sense, one which compares or juxtaposes
seemingly unrelated subjects. For
example, in Shakespeare’s Sonnet 73:
In me thou seest the glowing
of such fire,
That on the ashes of his
youth doth lie…
The narrator directly
transfers and applies the “dying ember” image in a new “foreign” sense: his own
awareness of his waning youth.
This is Aristotle’s
contribution to the standard substitution model of metaphor. It is to be
understood as a linguistic device, widely applied but remaining within the
confines of rhetoric and poetry. Though it does play a central role in social
persuasion, metaphor, restricted by the mechanics of similarity and
substitution, does not carry with it any speculative or philosophical
importance. Metaphors may point out underlying similarities between objects and
their descriptive categories, and may instruct through adding liveliness and
elegance to speech, but they do not refer, in the strong sense, to a form of
propositional knowledge.
The formal structure of
substitution operates in the following manner: the first subject or entity
under description in one context is characterized as equivalent in some way to
the second entity derived from another context; it is either implied or stated
that the first entity “is” the second entity in some way. The metaphorical
attribution occurs when certain select properties from the second entity are
imposed on the first in order to characterize it in some distinctive way.
Metaphor relies on pre-existing categories which classify objects and their
properties; these categories guide the ascription of predicates to objects, and
since metaphor may entail a kind of violation of this order, it cannot itself
refer to a “real” class of existing objects or the relations between them.
Similarly, in poetry, metaphor serves not as a foundation for knowledge, but as
a tool for mimesis or artistic imitation, representing the actions in epic
tragedy or mythos in order to move and instruct the emotions of the audience
for the purpose of catharsis.
Aristotle’s theory and its
significance for philosophy can only be fully understood in terms of the wider
context of denotation and reference which supports the classical realist
epistemology. Metaphor is found within his taxonomy of speech forms;
additionally, simile is subordinate to metaphor and both are figures of speech
falling under the rubric of lexis/diction, which itself is composed of
individual linguistic units or noun-names and verbs. Lexis operates within the
unity of logos, meaning that the uses of various forms of speech must conform
to the overall unity of language and reason, held together by categorical
structures of being found in Aristotle’s metaphysics.
As a result of Aristotle’s
combined thinking in these works, it turns out that the ostensive function of
naming individual objects (“this” name standing for “this object” or property)
allows for the clear demarcation between the literal and figurative meanings
for names. Thus, the noun-name can work as a signifier of meaning in two
domains, the literal and the non-literal. However, there remains an unresolved
problem: the categorical nature of the boundary between literal and figurative
domains will be a point of contention for many contemporary critiques of the
theory coming from phenomenological philosophy.
Furthermore, the denotative
theory has served in support of the referential function of language, one which
assumes a system of methodological connections between language, sense
perceptions, mental states, and the external world. The referential relation
between language and its objects serves the correspondence theory of truth, in
that the truth-bearing capacity of language corresponds to valid perception and
cognition of the external world. The theory assumes that these sets of
correspondences allow for the consistent and reliable relation of reference
between words, images, and objects.
Aristotle accounts for this
kind of correspondence in the following way: sense perceptions’s pathemata give
rise to the psychological states in which object representations are formed.
These states are actually likenesses (isomorphisms) of the external objects.
Thus, names for things refer to the things themselves, mental representations
of those things, and to the class-based meanings.
If, as Aristotle assumes,
the meaning of metaphor rests on the level of the noun-name, its distinguishing
feature lies in its deviation, a “something which happens” to the noun/name by
virtue of a transfer (epiphora) of meaning. Here, Aristotle creates a metaphor
(based on physical movement) in order to explain metaphor. The term “phora”
refers to a change in location from one place to another, to which is added the
prefix “epi:” epiphora refers then to the transfer of the common proper name of
the thing to the new, unfamiliar, alien (allotrios) place or object.
Furthermore, the transference (or substitution), borrowing as it does the alien
name for the thing, does not disrupt the overall unity of meaning or logical
order of correspondence within the denotative system; all such movement remains
within the classifications of genus and species.
The metaphoric transfer of
meaning will become a significant point of debate and speculation in later
philosophical discussions. Although Aristotle himself does not explore the
latent philosophical questions in his own theory, subsequent philosophers of
language have over the years recast these issues, exploring the challenges to
meaning, reference, and correspondence that present themselves in the
substitution theory. What happens, on these various levels, when we substitute
one object or descriptor of a “natural kind,” to a foreign object domain? It
may the be the case that metaphorical transference calls into question the
limits of all meaning-bearing categories, and in turn, the manner in which
words can be said to “refer” to specific objects and their attributes. By
virtue of the epiphoric movement, species and genus attributes of disparate
objects fall into relations of kinship, opposition, or deviation among the
various ontological categories. These relations allow for the metaphoric
novelty which will subsequently fuel the development of alternative theories,
those which view as fundamental to our cognitive or conceptual processes. At
this point the analysis of metaphor opens up the philosophical space for
further debate and interpretation.
b.
The Philosophical Issues
In any theory of metaphor,
there are significant philosophical implications for the transfer of meaning
from one object-domain or context of associations to another. The metaphor,
unlike its sister-trope the analogy, creates a new form of predication,
suggesting that one category or class of objects (with certain characteristics)
can be projected onto another separate class of entities; this projection may
require a blurring of the ontological and epistemological distinctions between
the kinds of objects that can be said to exist, either in the mind or in the
external world. Returning to the Shakespearean metaphor above, what are the
criteria that we use to determine whether a dying ember aptly fits the state of
the narrator’s consciousness? What are the perceptual and ontological
connections between fire and human existence? The first problem lies in how we
are to explain the initial “fit” between any predicate category and its
objects. Another problem comes to the forefront when we try to account for how
metaphors enable us to think in new ways. If we are to move beyond the standard
substitution model, we are compelled to investigate the specific mental
operations that enable us to create metaphoric representations; we need to
elaborate upon the processes which connect particular external objects (and
their properties) given to sensory experience to linguistic signs “referring”
to a new kind of object, knowledge context, or domain of experience.
According to the standard
model, a metaphor’s ability to signify is restricted by ordinary denotation.
The metaphor, understood as a new name, is conceived as a function of
individual terms, rather than sentences or wider forms of discourse
(narratives, texts). As Continental phenomenology develops in the late 19th and
20th centuries, we are presented with radically alternative theories which obscure
strict boundaries between the literal and the figurative, disrupting the
connections between perception, language, and thought. Namely, the
phenomenological, interactionist, and cognitive treatments of metaphor defend
the view that metaphorical language and symbol serve as indirect routes to
novel ways of knowing and describing human experience. In their own ways, these
theories will call into question the validity and usefulness of correspondence
and reference, especially in theoretical disciplines such as philosophy,
theology, literature, and science.
Although this article
largely focuses on explicating phenomenological theories of metaphor, it should
be noted that in all three theories mentioned above, metaphor is displaced from
its formerly secondary position in substitution theory to occupying the front
and center of our cognitive capabilities. Understood as the product of
intentional structures in the mind, metaphor now becomes conceptual, rather
than merely ornamental, acting as a conduit through which we take apart and
re-assemble the concepts we use to describe the varieties and nuances of
experience. They all share in the assumption that metaphors suggest, posit, or
disclose similarities between objects and domains of experience (where there seem
to be none), without explicitly recognizing that a comparison is being made
between two sometimes very different kinds of things or events. These theories,
when applied to our original metaphor (“in me thou seest…”) contend that at
times, there need not be any explicit similarity between states of awareness or
existence as “fire” or “ashes”.
c.
Nietzsche’s Role in Development of Phenomenological Theories of Metaphor
In Nietzsche’s thought we
see an early turning away from the substitution theory and its reliance on the
correspondence theory of truth, denotation, and reference. His description of
metaphor takes us back to its primordial “precognitive” or ontological origins;
Nietzsche acts here as a pre-cursor to later developments, yet in itself his analysis
offers a compelling account of the power of metaphor. Though his remarks on
metaphor are somewhat scattered, they can be found in the early writings of
1872-74, Nachgelassene Fragmente, and “On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral
Sense” (see W. Kaufman’s translation in The Portable Nietzsche). Together with
the “Rhetorik” lectures, these writings argue for a genealogical explanation of
the conceptual, displacing traditional philosophical categories into the
metaphorical realm. In doing so, he deconstructs our conventional reliance on
the idea that meaningful language must reflect a system of logical
correspondences.
With correspondence, we can
only assume we are in possession of the truth when our representations or ideas
about the world “match up” with external states of affairs. We have already
seen how Aristotle’s system of first-order predication supports correspondence,
as it is enabled through the denotative ascription of predicates/categorical
features of /to objects. But Nietzsche boldly suggests that we are, from the
outset, already in metaphor and he works from this starting point. The concepts
and judgments we use to describe reality do not flatly reflect pre-existing
similarities or causal relationships between themselves and our physical intuitions
about reality, they are themselves metaphorical constructions; that is, they
are creative forms of differentiation emerging out of a deeper undifferentiated
primordiality of being. The truth of the world is more closely reflected in the
Dionysian level of pure aesthetic immersion into an “undecipherable” innermost
essence of things.
Even in his early work, The
Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche rejects the long-held assumption that truth is an
ordering of concepts expressed through rigid linguistic categories, putting
forth the alternative view which gives primacy to symbol as the purest, most
elemental form of representation. That which is and must be expressed is
produced organically, out of the flux of nature and yielding a “becoming”
rather than being.
In the Dionysian dithyramb
man is incited to the greatest exaltation of all his symbolic faculties;
something never before experienced struggles for utterance—the annihilation of
the veil of maya, … oneness as the soul of the race and of nature itself. The
essence of nature is now to be expressed symbolically; we need a new world of
symbols.… (BOT Ch. 2)
Here, following
Schopenhauer, he reverses Aristotelian transference of concept-categories from
the literal to the figurative, and makes the figurative the original mode for
representation of experience. The class terms “species” and “genus”, based in
Aristotle and so important in classical and medieval epistemology, only appear
to originate and validate themselves in “dialectics and through scientific reflection.”
For Nietzsche, the categories hide their real nature, abiding as frozen
metaphors which reflect previously experienced levels of natural experience
metaphorically represented in our consciousness. They emerge through
construction indirectly based in vague images or names for things, willed into
being out of the unnamed flowing elements of biological existence. Even Thales
the pre-Socratic, we are reminded, in his attempt to give identity to the
underlying unity of all things, falls back on a conceptualization of it as
water without realizing he is using a metaphor.
Once we construct and begin
to apply our concepts, their metaphorical origins are forgotten or concealed
from ordinary awareness. This theoretical process is but another attempt to
restore “the also-forgotten” original unity of being. The layering of metaphors,
the archeological ancestors of concepts, is specifically linked to our
immediate experiential capacity to transcend the proper and the individual
levels of experience and linguistic signs. We cannot, argues Nietzsche,
construct metaphors without breaking out of the confines of singularity, thus
we must reject the artificiality of designating separate names for separate
things. To assume that an individual name would completely and transparently
describe its referent (in perception) is to also assume that language and
external experience mirror one another in some perfect way. It is rather the
case that language transfers meaning from place to place. The terms metapherein
and Übertragung are equivalently applied here; if external experience is in
constant flux, it is not possible to reduplicate exact and individual meanings.
To re-describe things through metaphor is to “leave out” and “carry-over”
meaning, to undergo a kind of dispossession of self, thing, place, and time and
an overcoming of both individualisms and dualities. Thus the meaningful
expression of the real is seen and experienced most directly in the endlessly
creative activity of art and music, rather than philosophy.
2.
The Phenomenological Theory in Continental Philosophy
Versions of Nietzsche’s
“metaphorization” of thought will reappear in the Continental philosophers
described below; those who owe their phenomenological attitudes to Husserl, but
disagree with his transcendental idealization of meaning, one which demands
that we somehow separate the world of experience from the essential meanings of
objects in that world. Taken together, these philosophers call into question
the position that truth entails a relationship of correspondence between dual
aspects of reality, one internal to our minds and the other external. We
consider Heidegger, Ricoeur, and Derrida as the primary examples. For
Heidegger, metaphoric language signals a totality or field of significance in
which being discloses or reveals itself. Ricoeur’s work, in turn, builds upon
aspects of Heidegger’s ontological hermeneutics, explicating how it is the case
that metaphors drive speculative reflection. In Ricoeur’s model, the literal
level is subverted, and metaphoric language and symbols containing “semantic
kernels” create structures of double reference in all figurative forms of
discourse. These structures point beyond themselves in symbols and texts,
serving as mediums which reveal new worlds of meaning and existential
possibilities.
French philosopher Jacques
Derrida, on the other hand, reiterates the Nietzschean position; metaphor does
not subvert metaphysics, but rather is itself the hidden source of all
conceptual structures.
a.
Phenomenological Method: Husserl
Edmund Husserl’s
phenomenological method laid the groundwork, in the early 20th century, for
what would eventually take shape in the phenomenological philosophies of Martin
Heidegger, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, and Jean-Paul Sartre. Husserl’s early work
provides the foundation for exploring how these modes of presentation convey
the actual meaningful contents of experience. He means to address here the
former distinction made by Kant between the phenomenal appearances of the real
(to consciousness) and the noumenal reality of the things-in-themselves.
Husserl, broadly speaking, seeks to resolve not only what some see as a
problematic dualism in Kant, but also some philosophical problems that
accompany Hegel’s constructivist phenomenology.
Taken in its entirety,
Husserl’s project demonstrates a major shift in the 20th century phenomenology,
seeking a rigorous method for the description and analysis of consciousness and
the contents given to it. He intends his method to be the scientific grounding
for philosophy; it is to be a critique of psychologism and a return to a universal
knowledge of “the things themselves,” those intelligible objects apprehended by
and given to consciousness.
In applying this method we
seek, Husserl argues, a scientific foundation for universally objective
knowledge; adhering to the “pure description” of phenomena given to
consciousness through the perception of objects. If those objects are knowable,
it is because they are immediate in conscious experience. It is through the
thorough description of these objects as they appear to us in terms of color,
shape, and so forth, that we apprehend that which is essential – what we call
“essences” or meanings. Here, the act of description is a method for avoiding a
metaphysical trap: that of imposing these essences or object meanings onto the
contents of mental experience. Noesis, for Husserl, achieves its aim by
including within itself (giving an account of) the role that context or horizon
plays in delineating possible objects for experience. This will have important
implications for later phenomenological theories of metaphor, in that metaphors
may be said intend new figurative contexts in which being appears to us in new
ways.
In Ideen (30), Husserl
explains how such a horizon or domain of experience presents a set of criteria
for us to apply. We choose and identify an object as a single member of a class
of objects, and so these regions of subjective experience, also called regions
of phenomena, circumscribe certain totalities or generic unities to which
concrete items belong. In order to understand the phenomenological approach to
meaning-making, it is first necessary to clarify what we mean by
“phenomenological description,” as it is described in Logical Investigations.
Drawing upon the work of Brentano and Meinong, Husserl develops a set of
necessary structural relations between the knower (ego), the objects of
experience, and the horizon within which those objects are given. The relation
is characterized in an axiomatic manner as intentionality, where the subjective
consciousness and its objects are correlates brought together in a
psychological act. Subjectivity contributes to and makes possible cognition;
specifically, it must be the case that perception and cognition are always
about something given in the stream of consciousness, they are only possible
because consciousness intends or refers to these immanent objects. As we shall
presently see, the intentional nature of consciousness applies to Ricoeur’s
hermeneutics of the understanding, bestowing metaphor with a special ability to
expand (to nearly undermining) the structure of reference in a non-literal
sense to an existential state.
Husserl’s stage like
development of phenomenology unveils the structure of intentionality as derived
from the careful description of certain mental acts. Communicable linguistic
expressions, such as names and sentences, exist only in so far as they exhibit
intentional meanings for speakers. Written or spoken expressions only carry
references to objects because they have meanings for speakers and knowers. If
we examine all of our mental perceptions, we find it impossible to think
without intending an object of some sort. Both Continental and Anglo-American
thinkers agree that metaphor holds the key to understanding these processes, as
it re-organizes our senses of perception, temporality, and relation of subject
to object, referring to these as subjects of existential concern and
possibility.
b.
Heidegger’s Contribution
Heidegger, building upon the
phenomenological thematic, asserts that philosophical analysis should keep to
careful description of the human encounter with the world, revealing the modes
in which being is existentially or relationally given. This signals both a nod
to and departure from Husserl, leading to a rethinking of phenomenology which
replaces the theoretical apprehension of meaning with an “uncovering” of being
as it is lived out in experiential contexts or horizons. Later, Ricoeur will
draw on Heidegger’s “existentialized” intentionality as he characterizes the
referential power of metaphors to signal those meanings waiting to be
“uncovered’ by Dasein’s (human as being-there) experience of itself – in
relation to others, and to alternate worlds of possibility.
As his student, Heidegger
owes to Husserl the phenomenological intent to capture “the things themselves”
(die Sachen selbst), however, the Heideggerian project outlined in Being and
Time rejects the attempt to establish phenomenology as a science of the
structures of consciousness and reforms it in ontologically disclosive or
manifestational terms. Heidegger’s strong attraction to the hermeneutic
tradition in part originates in his dialogue with Wilhem Dilthey, the 19th
century thinker who stressed the importance of historical consciousness
attitude in guiding the work of the social sciences and hermeneutics, directed
toward the understanding of primordial experience. Dilthey’s influence on
Heidegger and Ricoeur (as well as Gadamer) is evident, in that all recognize
the historical life of humans as apprehended in the study of the text (a form of
spirit), particularly those containing metaphors and narratives conveying a
lived, concrete experience of religious life.
Heidegger rejects the notion
that the structures of consciousness are internally maintained as
transcendentally subjective and also directed towards their transcendental
object. Phenomenology must now be tied to the problems of human existence, and
must then direct itself immediately towards the lived world and allow this
“beholding” of the world to guide the work of “its own uncovering.”
Heidegger argues for a
return to the original Greek definitions of the terms phainonmenon (derived
from phainesthai, or “that which shows itself”) and logos. Heidegger adopts
these terms for his own purposes, utilizing them to reinforce the dependence of
ontological disclosure or presence: those beings showing themselves or letting
themselves be “seen-as.” The pursuit of aletheia, (“truth as recovering of the
forgotten aspects of being”) is now fulfilled through adherence to a method of
self-interpretation achieved from the standpoint of Dasein’s (humanity’s)
subjectivity, which has come to replace the transcendental ego of Kant and
Husserl.
The turn to language, in
this case, must be more than simple communication between persons; it is a
primordial feature of subjectivity. Language is to be the interpretive medium
of the understanding through which all forms of being present themselves to
subjective apprehension. In this way, Heidegger replaces the transcendental
version of phenomenology with the disclosive, where the structure of
interpretation provides further insight into his ontological purposes of the
understanding.
3.
Existential Phenomenology: Paul Ricoeur, Hermeneutics, and Metaphor
The linguistic turn in
phenomenology has been most directly applied to metaphor in the works of Paul
Ricoeur, who revisits Husserlian and Heideggerian themes in his extensive
treatment of metaphor. He extends his analysis of metaphor into a fully developed
discursive theory of symbol, focusing on those found in religious texts and
sacred narratives. His own views follow from what he thinks are overly limited
structuralist theories of symbol, which, in essence, do not provide a theory of
linguistic reference useful for his own hermeneutic project. For Ricoeur, a
proper theory of metaphor understands it to be “a re-appropriation of our
effort to exist,” echoing Nietszche’s call to go back to the primordiality of
being. Metaphor must then include the notion that such language is expressive
and constitutive of the being of those who embark on philosophical reflection.
Much of Ricoeur’s thought
can be characterized by his well-known statement “the symbol gives rise to the
thought.” Ricoeur shares Heidegger’s and Husserl’s assumptions: we reflectively
apprehend or grasp the structures of human experience as they are presented to
temporalized subjective consciousness While the “pure” phenomenology of Husserl
seeks a transparent description of experience as it is lived out in phases or
moments, Ricoeur, also following Nietzsche, centers the creation of meaning in
the existential context. The noetic act originates in the encounter with a
living text, constituting “a horizon of possibilities,” for the meaning of
existence, thus abandoning the search for essences internal to the objects we
experience in the world.
His foundational work in The
Symbolism of Evil and The Rule of Metaphor places the route to human
understanding concretely, via symbolic expressions which allow for the
phenomenological constitution, reflection, and re-appropriation of experience.
These processes are enabled by the structure of “seeing-as,” adding to
Heidegger’s insight with the metaphoric acting as a “refiguring” of that which
is given to consciousness. At various points he enters into conversation with
Max Black and Nelson Goodman, among others, who also recognize the cognitive
contributions to science and art found in the models and metaphors. In
Ricoeur’s case, sacred metaphors display the same second-order functions shared
by those in the arts and sciences, but with a distinctively ontological
emphasis: “the interpretation of symbols is worthy of being called a
hermeneutics only insofar as it is a part of self-understanding and of the
understanding of being” (COI 30).
In The Rule of Metaphor,
Ricoeur, departing from Aristotle, locates the signifying power of metaphor
primarily at the level of the sentence, not individual terms. Metaphor is to be
understood as a discursive linguistic act which achieves its purpose through
extended predication rather than simple substitution of names. Ricoeur, like so
many language philosophers, argues that Aristotelian substitution is
incomplete; it does not go far enough in accounting for the semantic, syntactic,
logical, and ontological issues that accompany the creation of a metaphor. The
standard substitution model cannot do justice to potential for metaphor create
meaning by working in tandem with propositional thought-structures (sentences).
To these ends, Ricoeur’s study in The Rule of Metaphor replaces substitution
and strict denotative theories with a theory of language that works through a
structure of double reference.
Taking his lead while
diverging from Aristotle, Ricoeur reads the metaphorical transfer of a name as
a kind of “category mistake” which produces an imaginative construction about
the new way objects may be related to one another. He expands this dynamic of
“meaning transfer” on to the level of the sentence, then text, enabling the
production of a second-order discursive level of thinking whereby all forms of
symbolic language become phenomenological disclosures of being.
The discussion begins with
the linguistic movement of epiphora (transfer of names-predicates) taken from
an example in Poetics. A central dynamic exists in transposing one term, with
one set of meaning-associations onto another. Citing Aristotle’s own example of
“sowing around a god-created flame,”
If A = light of the sun, B =
action of the sun, C = grain, and D = sowing, then
B is to A, as D is to C
We see action of the sun is
to light as sowing is to grain, however, B is a vague action term (sun’s
action) which is both missing and implied; Ricoeur calls this a “nameless act”
which establishes a similar relation to the object, sunlight, as sowing is to
the grain. In this act the phenomenological space for the creation of new
meaning is opened up, precisely because we cannot find a conventional word to
take the place of a metaphorical word. The nameless act implies that the
transfer of an alien name entails more than a simple substitution of concepts,
and is therefore said to be logically disruptive.
a.
The Mechanics of Conceptual Blending
The “nameless act” entails a
kind of “cognitive leap:’’ since there is no conventional term for B, the act
does not involve substituting a decorative term in its place. Rather, a new
meaning association has been created through the semantic gap between the
objects. The absence of the original literal term, the “semantic void”, cannot be
filled without the creation of a metaphor which signals the larger discursive
context of the sentence and eventually, the text. If, as above, the transfer of
predicates (the sowing of grain as casting of flames) challenges the “rules” of
meaning dictated by ostensive theory, we are forced to make a new connection
where there was none, between the conventional and metaphorical names for the
object. For Ricoeur, the figurative (sowing around a flame) acts as hermeneutic
medium in that it negates and displaces the original term, signifying a “new
kind of object” which is in fact a new form (logos) of being. The metaphorical
statement allows us to say that an object is and is not what we usually call
it. The sense-based aspect is then “divorced” from predication and
subsequently, logos is emptied of its objective meaning; the new object may be
meaningful but not clear under the conditions of strict denotation or natural
knowledge.
We take note that the “new
object” (theoretically speaking) has more than figurative existence; the newly
formed subject-predicate relation places the copula at the center of the
name-object (ROM 18). Ricoeur’s objective is to create a dialectically driven
process which produces a new ‘object-domain’ or category of being. Following the
movement of the Hegelian Aufhebung, (through the aforementioned negation and
displacement) the new name has opened up a new field of meaning to be
re-appropriated into our reflective consciousness. This is how Ricoeur
deconstructs first-order reference in order to develop an ontology of sacred
language based on second-order reference.
We are led to the view that
myths are modes of discourse whose meanings are phenomenological spaces of
openness, creating a nearly infinite range of interpretations. Thus we see how
metaphor enables being, as Aristotle notes, to “be said in many ways.”
Ricoeur argues that
second-order discursivity “violates” the pre-existing first order of genus and
species, in turn causing a kind of upheaval among further relations and rules
set by the categories: namely subordination, coordination, proportionality or
equality among object properties. Something of a unity of being remains, yet
for Ricoeur this non-generic unity or enchainement, corresponds to a single
generic context referring to “Being,” restricting the senses or applications of
transferred predicates in the metaphoric context.
b.
The Role of Kant’s Schematism in Conceptual Blending
The notion of a “non-generic
unity” raises, perhaps, more philosophical problems than it answers. How are we
to explain the mechanics which blend descriptors from one object domain and its
sets of perceptions, to a domain of foreign objects? Ricoeur addresses the
epistemic issues surrounding the transfer of names from one category to another
in spatiotemporal experience by importing Kant’s theory of object construction,
found in the Critique of Pure Reason. In the “Transcendental Schematism”, Kant
establishes the objective validity of the conceptual categories we use to
synthesize the contents of experience. In this section, Kant elevates the
Aristotelian categories from grammatical principles to formal structures
intrinsic to reason. Here, he identifies an essential problem for knowledge:
how are we to conceive a relationship between these pure concept-categories of
the understanding and the sensible objects given to us in space and time? With
the introduction of the schematism, Kant seeks a resolution to the various
issues inherent to the construction of mental representations (a position
shared by contemporary cognitive scientists; see below). For Ricoeur, this
serves to answer the problem of how metaphoric representations of reality can
actually “refer” to reality (even if only at the existential level of
experience).
Kant states “the Schematism”
is a “sensible condition under which alone pure concepts of the understanding
can be employed” (CPR/A 136). Though the doctrine is sometimes said to be
notoriously confusing due to its circular nature, the schemata are meant as a
distinctive set of mediating representations, rules, or operators in the mind
which themselves display the universal and necessary characteristics of
sensible objects; these characteristics are in turn synthesized and unified by
the activity of the transcendental imagination.
In plainer terms, the
schematic function is used by the imagination to guide it in the construction
of images. It does not seem to be any kind of picture of an object, but rather
the “form” or “listing” of how we produce the picture. For Ricoeur, the
schematism lends the structural support for assigning an actual truth-value or
cognitive contribution to the semantic innovation produced by metaphor. The
construction of new meaning via new forms of predication entails a
re-organization and re-interpretation of pre-existing forms, and the operations
of the productive imagination enable the entire process.
In the work Figuring the
Sacred, for example, Ricoeur, answering to his contemporary Mircea Eliade ( The
Sacred and The Profane), moves metaphor beyond the natural “boundedness” of
myths and symbols. While these manifest meaning, they are still constrained in
that they must mirror the natural cosmic order of things. Metaphor, on the
other hand, occupies the center of a “hermeneutic of proclamation;” it has the
power to proclaim because it is a “free invention of discourse.” Ricoeur
specifically explicates biblical parables, proverbs, and eschatological
statements as extended metaphorical processes. Thus, “The Kingdom of God will
not come with signs that you can observe. Do not say, ‘It is here; it is
there.’ Behold the kingdom of God is among you” (Luke 17:20-21). This saying
creates meaning by breaking down our ordinary or familiar temporal frameworks
applied to interpretation of signs (of the kingdom). The quest for signs is,
according to Ricoeur, “overthrown” for the sake of “a completely new
existential signification” (FS 59).
This discussion follows from
the earlier work in The Rule of Metaphor, where the mechanics of representation
behind this linguistic act of “re-description” are further developed. The act
points us towards a novel ontological domain of human possibility, enabled
through new cognitive content. The linguistic act of creating a metaphor in
essence becomes a hermeneutic act directed towards a gap which must be bridged,
that between the abstract (considerations of reflection) understanding
(Verstehen) and the finite living out of life. In this way Ricoeur’s theory,
often contrasted with that of Derrida, takes metaphor beyond the mechanics of
substitution.
4.
Jacques Derrida: Metaphor as Metaphysics
In general, Derrida’s
deconstructive philosophy can be read as a radically alternative way of reading
philosophical texts and arguments, viewing them in a novel way through the lens
of a rhetorical methodology. This will amount to the taking apart of
established ways in which philosophers define perception, concept formation,
meaning, and reference.
Derrida, from the outset,
will call into question the assumption that the formation of concepts (logos)
somehow escapes the primordiality of language and the fundamentally
metaphorical-mythical nature of philosophical discourse. In a move which goes
much further than Ricoeur, Derrida argues for what Guiseseppe Stellardi so
aptly calls the “reverse metaphorization of concepts.” The reversal is such
that there can be no final separation between the linguistic-metaphorical and
the philosophical realms. These domains are co-constitutive of one another, in
the sense that either one cannot be fully theorized or made to fully or
transparently explain the meaning of the other. The result is that language
acquires a certain obscurity, ascendancy, and autonomy. It will permanently
elude our attempts to fix its meaning-making activity in foundational terms
which necessitate a transcendent or externalized (to language) unified being.
Derrida’s White Mythology
offers a penetrating critique of the common paradigm involving the nature of
concepts, posing the following questions: “Is there metaphor in the text of
philosophy, and if so, how?” Here, the history of philosophy is characterized
as an economy, a kind of “usury” where meaning and valuation are understood as
metaphorical processes involving “gain and loss.” The process is represented
through Derrida’s well-known image of the coin:
I was thinking how the
Metaphysicians, when they make a language for themselves, are like …
knife-grinders, who instead of knives and scissors, should put medals and coins
to the grindstone to efface … the value… When they have worked away till
nothing is visible in these crown pieces, neither King Edward, the Emperor
William, nor the Republic, they say: ‘These pieces have nothing either English,
German, or French about them; we have freed them from all limits of time and
space; they are not worth five shillings any more ; they are of inestimable
value, and their exchange value is extended indefinitely.’ (WM 210).
The “usury” of the sign (the
coin) signifies the passage from the physical to the metaphysical. Abstractions
now become “worn out” metaphors; they seem like defaced coins, their original,
finite values now replaced by a vague or rough idea of the meaning-images that
may have been present in the originals.
Such is the movement which
simultaneously creates and masks the construction of concepts. Concepts, whose
real origins have been forgotten, now only yield an empty sort of philosophical
promise – that of “the absolute”, the universalized, unlimited “surplus value”
achieved by the eradication of the sensory or momentarily given. Derrida reads
this process along a negative Hegelian line: the metaphysicians are most
attracted to “concepts in the negative, ab-solute, in-finite, non-Being” (WM 121).
That is, their love of the most abstract concept, made that way “by long and
universal use”, reveals a preference for the construction of a metaphysics of
Being. This is made possible via the movement of the Hegelian Aufhebung. The
German term refers to a dynamic of sublation where the dialectical, progressive
movement of consciousness overcomes and subsumes the particular, concrete
singularities of experience through successive moments of cognition. Derrida
levels a strong criticism against Hegel’s attempts to overcome difference,
arguing that consciousness as understood by Hegel takes on the quality of
building an oppressive sort of narrative, subsuming the particular and the
momentary under an artificial theoretical gaze. Derrida prefers giving theoretical
privilege to the negative; that is, to the systematic negation of all finite
determinations of meaning derived from particular aspects of particular beings.
Echoing Heidegger, Derrida
conceives of metaphysical constructs as indicative of the Western “logocentric
epoch” in philosophy. They depend for their existence on the machinery of
binary logic. They remain static due to our adherence to the meaning of ousia
(essence), the definition of being based on self-identitical substance, which
can only be predicated or expressed in either/or terms. Reference to being, in
this case, is constrained within the field of the proper and univocal. Both
Heidegger and Derrida, and to some degree Ricoeur seek to free reference from
these constraints. Unlike Heidegger, however, Derrida does not work from the
assumption that being indicates some unified primordial reality.
For Derrida, there lies
hidden within the merely apparent logical unity (with its attendant binary
oppositions) or logocentricity of consciousness a white mythology, masking the
primitive plurivocity of being which eludes all attempts to name it. Here we
find traces of lost meanings, reminiscent of the lost inscriptions on coins.
These are “philosophemes,” words, tropes or modes of figuration which do not
express ideas or abstract representations of things (grounded in categories),
but rather invoke a radically plurivocal notion of meaning. Having thus
dismantled the logic of either/or with difference (difference), Derrida gives
priority to ambiguity, in “both/and” and “neither/nor” modes of thought and
expression. Meaning must then be constituted of and by difference, rather than
identity, for difference subverts all preconceived theoretical or ontological
structures. It is articulated in the context of all linguistic relations and
involves ongoing displacement of a final idealized and unified form of meaning;
such displacement reveals through hints and traces, the reality and experience
of a disruptive alterity in meaning and being. Alterity is “always already
there” by virtue of the presence of the Other.
With the introduction of
“the white mythology,” Derrida’s alignment with Nietszche creates a strong
opposition to traditional Western theoria. Forms of abstract ideation and
theoretical systems representing the oppressive consciousness of the “white
man,” built in the name of reason/logos, are in themselves a collection of
analogies, existing as colorless dead metaphors whose primitive origins lie in
the figurative realms of myths, symbol, and fable.
Derrida’s project, resulting
as it does in the deconstruction of metaphysics, runs counter to Ricoeur’s
tensive theory. In contrast to Heidegger’s restrained criticism Derrida’s
deconstruction appears to Ricoeur “unbounded.” That is, Ricoeur still assumes a
distinction between the speculative and the poetic, where the poetic “drives
the speculative” to explicate a surplus of meaning. The surplus, or plurivocity
is problematic from Derrida’s standpoint. The latter argues that the theory
remains logocentric in that it remains true to the binary mode of identity and
difference which underlie metaphysical distinctions such as “being and
non-being.” For Ricoeur, metaphors create a new space for meaning based on the
tension between that which is (can be properly predicated of an object) and
that which “is not” (which cannot be predicated of an object). Derrida begs to
differ: in the final analysis, there can be no such separation, systematic
philosophical theory or set of conceptual structures through which we subsume
and “explain” the cognitive or existential value of metaphor.
Derrida’s reverse
metaphorization of concepts does not support a plurivocal characterization of
meaning and being, it does not posit a wider referential field; for Derrida
metaphors and concepts remain in a complex, always ambiguous relation to one
another. Thus he seems to do away with “reference,” or the distinction between
signifier and signified, moving even beyond polysemy (the many potential
meaning that words carry). The point here is to preserve the flux of sense and
the ongoing dissemination of meaning and otherness.
a.
The Dispute between Ricoeur and Derrida
The dispute between Ricoeur
and Derrida regarding the referential power of metaphor lies in where they
position themselves with regard to Aristotle. Ricoeur’s position, in giving
priority to the noun-phrase instead of the singular name, challenges Aristotle
while still appealing to the original taxonomy (categories) of being based on
an architectonic system of predication. For Ricoeur, metaphoric signification
mimics the fundamentally equivocal nature of being—we cannot escape the
ontological implications of Aristotle’s statement: being can be “said in many
ways.” Nevertheless, Ricoeur maintains the distinction between mythos and
logos, for we need the tools provided by speculative discourse to explain the
polysemic value of metaphors.
Derrida’s deconstruction
reaches back to dismantle Aristotle’s theory, rooted as it is in the ontology
of the proper name/noun (onoma) which signifies a thing as self-identical being
(homousion). This, states Derrida, “reassembles and reflects the culture of the
West; the white man takes his own mythology, Indo-European mythology, his own
logos, that is, the mythos of his idiom, for the universal form of that he must
still wish to call Reason” (WM 213).
The original theory makes
metaphor yet another link in the logocentric chain—a form of metaphysical
oppression. If the value of metaphor is restricted to the transference of
names, then metaphor entails a loss or negation of the literal which is still
under the confines of a notion of discourse which upholds the traditional
formulations of representation and reference in terms of the mimetic and the
“proper” which are, in turn, based on a theory of perception (and an attendant
metaphysics) that gives priority to resemblance, identity, or what we can call
“the law of the same.”
5.
Anglo-American Philosophy: Interactionist Theories
Contemporary
phenomenological theories of metaphor directly challenge the straightforward
theory of reference, replacing the ordinary propositional truth based on
denotation with a theory of language which designates and discloses its
referents. These interactionist theories carry certain Neo-Kantian features,
particularly in the work of the analytic philosophers Nelson Goodman and Max
Black. They posit the view that metaphors can reorganize the connections we
make between our perceptions of the world. Their theories reflect certain
phenomenological assumptions about the ways in which figurative language
expands the referential field, allowing for the creation of novel meanings and
creating new possibilities for constructing models of reality; in moving
between the realms of art and science, metaphors have an interdisciplinary utility.
Both Goodman and Black continue to challenge the traditional theory of
linguistic reference, offering instead the argument that reference is enabled
by the manipulation of predicates in figurative modes of thinking through
language.
6.
Metaphor, Phenomenology, and Cognitive Science
Recent studies underscore
the connections between metaphors, mapping, and schematizing aspects of
cognitive organization in mental life. Husserl’s approach to cognition took an
anti-naturalist stance, opposed to defining consciousness as an objective
entity and therefore unsuited to studying the workings of subjective
consciousness; instead his phenomenological stance gave priority to
subjectivity, since it constitutes the necessary set of pre-conditions for
knowing anything at all as an object or a meaning. Recently, the trend has been
renewed and phenomenology has made some productive inroads into the examination
of connectionist and embodied approaches to perception, cognition and other
sorts of dynamic and adaptive (biological) systems.
Zahavi and Thompson, for
example, see strong links between Husserlian phenomenology and philosophy of
mind with respect to the phenomena of consciousness, where the constitutive
nature of subjective consciousness is clarified specifically in terms of the
forms and relations of different kinds of intentional mental states. These
involve the unity of temporal experience, the structural relations between
intentional mental acts and their objects, and the inherently embodied nature
of cognition. Those who study the embodied mind do not all operate in agreement
with traditional phenomenological assumptions and methods. Nevertheless, some
“naturalized” versions in the field of consciousness studies are now gaining
ground, offering viable solutions to the kind of problematic Cartesian
dualistic metaphysics that Husserl’s phenomenology suggests.
a.
The Embodied Mind
In recent years, the
expanding field of cognitive science has explored the role of metaphor in the
formation of consciousness (cognition and perception). In a general sense, it
appears that contemporary cognitivist, constructivist, and systems (as in
self-organizing) approaches to the study of mind incorporate metaphor as a tool
for developing an anti-metaphysical, anti-positivist theory of mind, in an
attempt to reject any residual Cartesian and Kantian psychologies. The
cognitive theories, however, remain partially in debt to Kantian schematism and
its role in cognition.
There is furthermore in
these theories an overturning of any remaining structuralist suppositions (that
language and meaning might be based on autonomous configurations of syntactic
elements). Many cognitive scientists, in disagreement with Chomsky’s generative
grammar, study meaning as a form of cognition that is activated in context of
use. Lakoff and Johnson, in Philosophy in the Flesh, find a great deal of
empirical evidence for the ways in which metaphors shape our ordinary
experience, exploring the largely unconscious perceptual and linguistic
processes that allow us to understand one idea or domain of experience, both
conceptual and physical, in terms of a “foreign” domain. The research follows
the work of Srini Narayanan and Eleanor Rosch, cognitive scientists who also
examine schemas and metaphors as key in embodied theories of cognition. Such
theories generally trace the connective interplay between our neuronal makeup,
or physical interactions with the environment, and our own private and social
human purposes.
In a limited sense, the
stress on the embodied nature of cognition aligns itself with the
phenomenological position. Perceptual systems, built in physical response to
determinate spatio-temporal and linguistic contexts, become phenomenological
“spaces” shaped through language use. Yet these researchers largely take issue
with Continental phenomenology and traditional philosophy in a dramatic and
far-reaching way, objecting to the claim that the phenomenological method of
introspection makes adequate space for our ability to survey and describe all available
fields of consciousness in the observing subject. If it is the case that we do
not fully access the far reaches of hidden cognitive processes, much of the
metaphorical mapping which underlies cognition takes place at an unconscious
level, which is sometimes referred to as “the cognitive unconscious.”(PIF
12-15)
Other philosophers of mind,
including Stefano Arduini, and Antonio D’Amasio, work along similar lines in
cognitive linguistics, cognitive science, neuroscience, and artificial
intelligence. Their work investigates the ways in which metaphors ground
various first and second-order cognitive and emotional operations and
functions. Their conclusions share insights with the Continental studies
conceiving of metaphor as a “refiguring” of experience. There is then some
potential for overlap with this cognitive-conceptual version of metaphor, where
metaphors and schemata embody emergent transformative categories enabling the
creation of new fields of cognition and meaning.
Arduini, in his work, has
explored what he calls the “anthropological ability” to build up
representations of the world. Here rhetorical figures are realized on the basis
of conceptual domains which create the borders of experience. We have access to
a kind of reality that would otherwise be indeterminate, for human beings have
the ability to conceptualize the world in imaginative terms through myth,
symbol, the unconscious, or any expressive sign. For Arduini, figurative
activity does not depict the given world, but allows for the ability to
construct world images employed in reality. To be figuratively competent is to
use the imagination as a tool which puts patterns together in inventive mental
processes. Arduini then seems to recall Nieztsche; anthropologically speaking,
humans are always engaging in some form of figuration or form of language,
which allows for “cognitive competence” in that it chooses among particular
forms which serve to define the surrounding contexts or environments. Again,
metaphor is foundational to the apprehension of reality; it is part of the
pre-reflective or primordial apparatus of experience, perception, and first-
through second-order thought, comprising an entire theoretical approach as well
as disciplines such as evolutionary anthropology (see Tooby and Cosmides).
b.
The Literary Mind
The work of Gilles
Fauconnier and Mark Turner extends that of Lakoff and Johnson outlined above.
For Fauconnier, the task of language is to construct, and for the linguist and
cognitive scientist it is “a window into the mind.” Independently and together,
Fauconnier and Turner’s collaboration results in a theory of conceptual
blending in which metaphorical forms take center stage. Basically, the theory
of conceptual blending follows from Lakoff and Johnson’s work on the “mapping”
or projective qualities of our cognitive faculties. For example, if we return
to take Shakespearean line “in me thou seest the glowing of such fire”, the
source is fire, whose sets of associations are projected onto the target – in
this case the waning aspect of the narrator. Their research shows that large
numbers of such cross-domain mappings are expressed as conceptual structures
which have propositional content: for example, “life is fire, loss is
extinction of fire.” There exist several categories of mappings across
different conceptual domains, including spatio-temporal orientation, movement,
and containment. For example: “time flies” or “this relationship is
smothering.”
Turner’s work in The
Literary Mind, takes a slightly different route, portraying these cognitive
mechanisms as forms of “storytelling.” This may, superficially, seem
counterintuitive to the ordinary observer, but Turner gives ample evidence for
the mind’s ability to do much of its everyday work using various forms of
narrative projection (LM 6-9). It is not too far a reach from this version of
narrative connection back to the hermeneutic and cognitive-conceptual uses of
metaphor outlined earlier. If we understand parables to be essentially forms of
extended metaphor, we can clearly see the various ways in which they contribute
to the making of intelligible experience.
The study of these mental
models sheds light on the phenomenological and hermeneutic aspects of
reality-construction. If these heuristic models are necessary to cognitive
functioning, it is because they allow us to represent higher-order aspects of
reality which involve expressions of human agency, intentionality, and
motivation. Though we may be largely unaware of these patterns, they are based
on our ability to think in metaphor, are necessary, and are continuously
working to enable the structuring of intentional experience – which cannot
always be adequately represented by straightforward first-order physical
description. Fauconnier states:
We see their status as
inventions by contrasting them with alternative representations of the world.
When we watch someone sitting down in a chair, we see what physics cannot
recognize: an animate agent performing an intentional act. (MTL 19-20)
Turner, along with
Fauconnier and Lakoff, connects parabolic thought with the image-schematic or
mapping between different domains of encounter with our environments.
Fauconnier’s work, correlating here with Turner’s, moves between
cognitive-scientific and phenomenological considerations; both depict mapping
as a constrained form of projection, a complex mental manipulation which moves
across mental structures which correspond to various phenomenological spaces of
thought, action, and communication.
Metaphorical mapping allows
the mind to cross and conflate several domains of experience. The
cross-referencing, reminiscent of Black’s interactionist dynamics, amounts to a
form of induction resulting from projected relations between a source
structure, a pattern we already understand, onto a target structure, that which
we seek to understand.
Mapping as a form of
metaphoric construction leads to other forms of blending, conceptual
integration, and novel category formation. We can, along with Fauconnier and
the rest, describe this emergent evolution of linguistic meaning in dialectical
terms, arguing that it is possible to mesh together two images of virus
(biological and computational) into a third integrated idea that integrates and
expands the meaning of the first two (MTL 22). Philosophically speaking, we
seem to have come full circle back to the Hegelian theme which runs through the
phenomenological analysis of metaphor as a re-mapping of mind and reality.
7.
Conclusion
The Continental theories of
metaphor that have extrapolated and developed variations on the theme expressed
in Nietzsche’s apocryphal pronouncement that truth is “a mobile army of
metaphors.” The notion that metaphorical language is somehow ontologically and
epistemologically prior to ordinary propositional language has since been
voiced by Heidegger, Ricoeur, and Derrida. For these thinkers metaphor serves
as a foundational heuristic structure, one which is primarily designed to
subvert ordinary reference and in some way dismantle the truth-bearing claims
of first-order propositional language. Martin Heidegger’s existential
phenomenology does away with the assumption that true or meaningful intentional
statements reflect epistemic judgments about the world; that is, they do not
derive referential efficacy through the assumed correspondence between an
internal idea and an external object. While there may be a kind of agreement
between our notions of things and the world in which we find those things, it
is still a derivative agreement emerging from a deeper ontologically determined
set of relations between things-in-the-world, given or presented to us as
inherently linked together in particular historical, linguistic, or cultural
contexts.
The role of metaphor in
perception and cognition also dominates the work of contemporary cognitive
scientists, linguists, and those working in the related fields of evolutionary
anthropology and computational theory. While the latter may not be directly
associated with Continental phenomenology, aspects of their work support an
“anti-metaphysical” position and draw upon common phenomenological themes which
stress the embodied, linguistic, contextual, and symbolic nature of knowledge.
Thinkers and researchers in this camp argue that metaphoric schemas are integral
to human reasoning and action, in that they allow us to develop our cognitive
and heuristic capacities beyond simple and direct first order experience.
No comments:
Post a Comment