Autonomy is an individual’s capacity for self-determination or
self-governance. Beyond that, it is a much-contested concept that comes up in a
number of different arenas. For example, there is the folk concept of autonomy,
which usually operates as an inchoate desire for freedom in some area of one’s
life, and which may or may not be connected with the agent’s idea of the moral
good. This folk concept of autonomy blurs the distinctions that philosophers
draw among personal autonomy, moral autonomy, and political autonomy. Moral
autonomy, usually traced back to Kant, is the capacity to deliberate and to
give oneself the moral law, rather than merely heeding the injunctions of
others. Personal autonomy is the capacity to decide for oneself and pursue a
course of action in one’s life, often regardless of any particular moral
content. Political autonomy is the property of having one’s decisions
respected, honored, and heeded within a political context.
Another distinction that can be made is between autonomy as a bare
capacity to make decisions and of autonomy as an ideal. When autonomy functions
as an ideal, agents who do not meet certain criteria in having reached a
decision are deemed non-autonomous with respect to that decision. This can
function both locally, in terms of particular actions, and globally, in terms
of agents as a whole. For instance, children, agents with cognitive
disabilities of a certain kind, or members of oppressed groups have been deemed
non-autonomous because of their inability to fulfill certain criteria of
autonomous agency, due to individual or social constraints.
There is debate over whether autonomy needs to be representative of a
kind of “authentic” or “true” self. This debate is often connected to whether
the autonomy theorist believes that an “authentic” or “true” self exists. In
fact, conceptions of autonomy are often connected to conceptions of the nature
of the self and its constitution. Theorists who hold a socially constituted
view of the self will have a different idea of autonomy (sometimes even denying
its existence altogether) than theorists who think that there can be some sort
of core “true” self, or that selves as agents can be considered in abstraction
from relational and social commitments and contexts.
Finally, autonomy has been criticized as being a bad ideal, for
promoting a pernicious model of human individuality that overlooks the
importance of social relationships and dependency. Responses to these
criticisms have come in various forms, but for the most part philosophers of
autonomy have striven to express the compatibility of the social aspects of
human action within their conceptions of self-determination, arguing that there
need not necessarily be an antagonism between social and relational ties, and
our ability to decide our own course of action.
This article will focus primarily on autonomy at the level of the
individual and the work being done on personal autonomy, but will also address
the connection of autonomy to issues in bioethics and political theory.
1. The History of Autonomy
a. Before Kant
The roots of autonomy as self-determination can be found in ancient
Greek philosophy, in the idea of self-mastery. For both Plato and Aristotle,
the most essentially human part of the soul is the rational part, illustrated
by Plato’s representation of this part as a human, rather than a lion or
many-headed beast, in his description of the tripartite soul in the Republic. A
just soul, for Plato, is one in which this rational human part governs over the
two others. Aristotle identifies the rational part of the soul as most truly a
person’s own in the Nicomachean Ethics (1166a17-19).
Plato and Aristotle also both associate the ideal for humanity with
self-sufficiency and a lack of dependency on others. For Aristotle,
self-sufficiency, or autarkeia, is an essential ingredient of happiness, and
involves a lack of dependence upon external conditions for happiness. The best
human will be one who is ruled by reason, and is not dependent upon others for
his or her happiness.
This ideal continues through Stoic philosophy and can be seen in the
early modern philosophy of Spinoza. The concept of autonomy itself continued to
develop in the modern period with the decrease of religious authority and the
increase of political liberty and emphasis on individual reason. Rousseau’s
idea of moral liberty, as mastery over oneself, is connected with civil liberty
and the ability to participate in legislation.
b. Kant
Kant further developed the idea of moral autonomy as having authority
over one’s actions. Rather than letting the principles by which we make
decisions be determined by our political leaders, pastors, or society, Kant
called upon the will to determine its guiding principles for itself, thus
connecting the idea of self-government to morality; instead of being obedient to
an externally imposed law or religious precept, one should be obedient to one’s
own self-imposed law. The former he
called heteronomy; the latter autonomy. In his “What is Enlightenment” essay,
he described enlightenment as “the human being’s emergence from his
self-incurred minority” and called on his readers to have the courage to use
their own understanding “without direction from another” (Kant 1996, 17). This
description is close to what we might acknowledge today as personal autonomy,
but Kant’s account is firmly located within his moral philosophy.
In acting we are guided by maxims, which are the subjective principles
by which we might personally choose to abide. If these maxims can be deemed
universal, such that they would be assented to and willed by any rational
being, and thus not rooted in any individual’s particular contingent
experience, then they may gain the status of objective laws of morality. Each
moral agent, then, is to be seen as a lawgiver in a community where others are
also lawgivers in their own right, and hence are to be respected as ends in
themselves; Kant calls this community the kingdom of ends.
While the will is supposed to be autonomous, for Kant, it is also not
supposed to be arbitrary or particularistic in its determinations. He sees our
inclinations and emotional responses as external to the process of the will’s
self-legislation; consequently, letting them determine our actions is
heteronomous rather than autonomous. Feelings, emotions, habits, and other
non-intellectual factors are excluded from autonomous decision-making. Any
circumstances that particularize us are also excluded from autonomous
decision-making.
The reason for Kant’s exclusion of feelings, inclinations, and other
particular aspects of our lives from the structure of autonomy is rooted in his
metaphysical account of the human being, which radically separates the
phenomenal human self from the noumenal human self. All empirical aspects of
our selfhood — all aspects of our experience — are part of the phenomenal self,
and subject to the deterministic laws of natural causality. Our freedom, on the
other hand, cannot be perceived or understood; rather we must posit the freedom
of the will as the basis for our ability to act morally.
Contemporary Kantians within moral theory do not adhere to Kant’s
metaphysics, but seek to understand how something like Kant’s conception of
autonomy can still stand today. Thomas Hill suggests, for example, that the
separation of our free will from our empirical selfhood be taken less as a
metaphysical idea but as a normative claim about what ought to count as reasons
for acting (Hill 1989, 96-97)
There are significant differences between Kant’s conception of moral
autonomy and the conceptions of personal autonomy developed within the last
thirty years, which attempt to articulate how social and cultural influences
can be compatible with autonomous decision-making. Further, the majority of
contemporary theories of personal autonomy are content-neutral accounts of
autonomy which are unconcerned with whether or not a person is acting according
to moral laws; they focus more on determining whether or not a person is acting
for his or her own reasons than on putting any restrictions on autonomous
action.
c. The Development of Individualism
in Autonomy
Between Kant’s description of moral autonomy and the recent scholarship
on personal autonomy, however, there was a process of individualizing the idea
of autonomy. The Romantics, reacting against the emphasis on the universality
of reason put forth by the Enlightenment, of which Kant’s philosophy was a
part, prized particularity and individuality. They highlighted the role of the
passions and emotions over reason, and the importance of developing one’s own
unique self. John Stuart Mill also praised and defended the development and
cultivation of individuality as worthwhile in itself, writing that “A person
whose desires and impulses are his own – are the expression of his own nature,
as it has been developed and modified by his own culture – is said to have a
character. One whose desires and impulses are not his own has no character, no
more than a steam engine has a character” (Mill 1956, 73).
The Romantic conception of individuality was then echoed within the
conception of authenticity that runs through phenomenological and existential
philosophy. Heidegger posits an inner call of conscience summoning us away from
‘das Man’: in order to be authentic, we need to heed this inner call and break
away from inauthentically following the crowd. This conception of authenticity
became intertwined with the idea of autonomy: both involve a call to think for
oneself and contain a streak of individualism (see Hinchman 1996).
Unlike the universalism espoused by Kantian autonomy, however,
authenticity, like the Romantic view, involves a call to be one’s own person,
not merely to think for oneself. For Kant, thinking for oneself would, if
undertaken properly, lead to universalizing one’s maxims; for both the
Romantics and the Existentialists, as well as for Mill, there is no such
expectation. This division is still present in the contrast between conceiving
of autonomy as a key feature of moral motivation, and autonomy as
self-expression and development of individual practical identity.
The emphasis on autonomy within this strain of philosophy was criticized
by Emmanuel Lévinas, who sees autonomy as part of our selfish and close-minded
desire to strive toward our own fulfillment and self-gratification rather than
being open to the disruptive call of the other’s needs (Lévinas 1969). He
argues for the value of heteronomy over autonomy. For Lévinas, in heteronomy,
the transcendent face of the other calls the ego into question, and the self
realizes its unchosen responsibility and obligation to the other. The self is
hence not self-legislating, but is determined by the call of the other. This
criticism of the basic structure of autonomy has been taken up within
continental ethics, which attempts to determine how or whether a practical,
normative ethics could be developed within this framework (see for example
Critchley 2007).
d. Autonomy and Psychological
Development
The connection between autonomy and the ideal of developing one’s own
individual self was adopted within the humanistic psychologies of Abraham
Maslow and Carl Rogers, who saw the goal of human development as
“self-actualization” and “becoming a person,” respectively. For Maslow and
Rogers, the most developed person is the most autonomous, and autonomy is
explicitly associated with not being dependent on others.
More recently Lawrence Kohlberg developed an account of moral
psychological development, in which more developed agents display a greater
amount of moral autonomy and independence in their judgments. The highest level
bears a great resemblance to the Kantian moral ideal, in its reference to
adopting universal values and standards as one’s own.
Kohlberg’s work was criticized by Carol Gilligan, who argued that this
pattern reflected male development, but not female. Instead of taking “steps
toward autonomy and independence,” in which “separation itself becomes the
model and the measure of growth,” “for women, identity has as much to do with
intimacy as with separation” (Gilligan 1982, 98). The trajectory is thus less
about individualization and independence than toward ultimately balancing and
harmonizing an agent’s interests with those of others.
Gilligan does not entirely repudiate autonomy itself as a value, but she
also does not suggest how it can be distinguished from the ideals of
independence and separation from others. Her critiques have been widely
influential and have played a major role in provoking work on feminist ethics
and, despite her criticism of the ideal of autonomy, conceptions of “relational
autonomy.”
The contemporary literature on personal autonomy within philosophy tends
to avoid these psychological ideas of individual development and
self-actualization. For the most part, it adopts a content-neutral approach
that rejects any particular developmental criteria for autonomous action, and
is more concerned with articulating the structure by which particular actions
can be deemed autonomous (or, conversely, the structure by which an agent can
be deemed autonomous with respect to particular actions).
2. Personal Autonomy
The contemporary discussion of personal autonomy can primarily be
distinguished from Kantian moral autonomy through its commitment to
metaphysical neutrality. Related to this is the adherence to at least a
procedural individualism: within contemporary personal autonomy accounts, an
action is not judged to be autonomous because of its rootedness in universal
principles, but based on features of the action and decision-making process
purely internal and particular to the individual agent.
The main distinction within personal autonomy is that between
content-neutral accounts, which do not specify any particular values or principles
that must be endorsed by the autonomous agent, and substantive accounts which
specify some particular value or values that must be included within autonomous
decision-making.
a. Content-Neutral or Procedural
Accounts
Content-neutral accounts, also called procedural, are those which deem a
particular action autonomous if it has been endorsed by a process of critical
reflection. These represent the majority of accounts of personal autonomy.
Procedural accounts determine criteria by which an agent’s actions can be said
to be autonomous, that do not depend on any particular conception of what kinds
of actions are autonomous or what kinds of agents are autonomous. They are
neutral with respect to what an agent might conceive of as good or might be trying
to achieve.
i. Hierarchical Procedural
Accounts
The beginning of the contemporary discussion of personal autonomy is in
the 1970s works of Harry Frankfurt and Gerald Dworkin. Their concern was to
give an account of what kind of individual freedom ought to be protected, and
how that moral freedom may be described in the context of contemporary
conceptions of free will. Their insight was that our decisions are worth
protecting if they are somehow rooted in our values and overall commitments and
objectives, and that they are not worth protecting if they run counter to those
values, commitments, and objectives. The concept of personal autonomy, thus,
can be used as a way of protecting certain decisions from paternalistic
interference. We may not necessarily want to honor the decision of a
weak-willed person who decides to do something against their better judgment
and against their conscious desire to do otherwise, whereas we do want to
protect a person’s decision to pursue an action that accords with their self-consciously
held values, even if it is not what we ourselves would have done. Frankfurt and
Dworkin phrase this insight in terms of a hierarchy of desires.
Frankfurt’s and Dworkin’s hierarchical accounts of autonomy form the
basis upon which the mainstream discussion builds and reacts against. Roughly
speaking, according to this hierarchical model, an agent is autonomous with
respect to an action on the condition that his or her first-order desire to
commit the act is sanctioned by a second-order volition endorsing the
first-order desire (see Frankfurt 1988, 12-25). This account is neutral with
respect to what the origins of the higher-order desires may be, and thus does
not exclude values and desires that are socially or relationally constituted.
The cause of such desires does not matter, solely the agent’s identification
with them (Frankfurt 1988, 53-54). Autonomy includes our ability to consider
and ask whether we do, in fact, identify with our desires or whether we might
wish to override them (Dworkin 1988).
The “we”, in this case, is constituted by our higher-order preferences;
Dworkin speaks of them as the agent’s “true self” (Dworkin 1989, 59).
ii. Criticisms of Hierarchical
Accounts
There are several different objections to the hierarchical model, mostly
revolving around the problem in locating the source of an agent’s autonomy, and
questioning the idea that autonomy can be located somehow in the process of
reflective endorsement itself.
First, the Problem of Manipulation criticism points out that because
Frankfurt’s account is ahistorical, it does not protect against the possibility
that someone, such as a hypnotist, may have interfered with the agent’s
second-order desires. We would hesitate to call such a hypnotized or
mind-controlled agent autonomous with respect to his or her actions under these
circumstances, but since the hierarchical model does not specify where or how
the second order volitions ought to be generated, it cannot adequately
distinguish between an autonomous agent and a mind-controlled one. The
structure of autonomous agency therefore seems to have a historical dimension
to it, since the history of how we developed or generated our volitions seems
to matter (see Mele 2001, 144-173).
John Christman develops a historical model of autonomy in order to
rectify this problem, such that the means and historical process by which an
agent reaches certain decisions is used in determining his or her status as
autonomous or not (Christman 1991). This way, an agent brainwashed into having
desire X would be deemed nonautonomous with respect to X. The theory runs into difficulty in a case
where an agent might freely choose to give up his or her autonomy, or conversely
where an agent might endorse a desire but not endorse the means by which he or
she was forced into developing the desire (see Taylor 2005, 10-12), but at
least it draws attention to some of the temporal features of autonomous agency.
Another criticism of the hierarchical model is the Regress or
Incompleteness Problem. According to Frankfurt and Dworkin, an agent is
autonomous with respect to his or her first order desires as long as they are
endorsed by second-order desires. However, this raises the question of the
source of the second-order volitions; if they themselves rely on third-order
volitions, and so on, then there is the danger of an infinite regress in
determining the source of the autonomous endorsement (see Watson 1975). If the
second order desires are autonomous for some other reason than a higher-order
volition, then the hierarchical model is incomplete in its explanation of
autonomy. Frankfurt, while acknowledging that there is “no theoretical limit”
to the series of higher order desires, holds that the series can end with an
agent’s “decisive commitment” to one of the first order desires (Frankfurt
1988, 21). However, the choice of terminating the series is itself arbitrary if
there no reason behind it (Watson 1975).
Frankfurt responds to this criticism in “Identification and
Wholeheartedness” by defining a decisive commitment as one which the agent
makes without reservation, and where the agent feels no reason to continue
deliberating (Frankfurt 1988, 168-9). To stop at this point is, Frankfurt
argues, hardly arbitrary. It is possible that the agent is mistaken in his or
her judgment, but that is always a possibility in deliberation, and thus not an
obstacle to Frankfurt’s theory in particular. In making a decision, an agent
“also seeks thereby to overcome or to supersede a condition of inner division
and to make himself into an integrated whole” (Frankfurt 1988, 174). Thus, by
making this decision, the agent has endorsed an intention that establishes “a
constraint by which other preferences and decisions are to be guided” (Frankfurt
1988, 175), and thus is self-determining and autonomous.
The criterion of wholeheartedness and unified agency has been criticized
by Diana Meyers, who argues for a decentered, fivefold notion of the subject,
which includes the unitary, decision-making self, but also acknowledges the
functions of the self as divided, as relational, as social, as embodied, and as
unconscious (Meyers 2005). The ideal of wholeheartedness has also been
criticized on the grounds that it does not reflect the agency of agents from
oppressed groups or from mixed traditions. Edwina Barvosa-Carter sees
ambivalence as an inescapable feature of much decision-making, especially for
mixed-race individuals who have inherited conflicting values, commitments, and
traditions (Barvosa-Carter 2007). Marina Oshana makes a similar point, with
reference to living within a racist society (Oshana 2005).
In any case, it is a puzzle how decisive commitments or higher-order
desires acquire their authority without themselves being endorsed, since
deriving authority from external manipulation would seem to undermine this
authority. This is the Ab Initio Problem: If the source of an agent’s autonomy
is ultimately something that can’t itself be reflectively endorsed, then the
agent’s autonomy seems to originate with something with respect to which he or
she is non-autonomous, something that falls outside the hierarchical model.
A related objection to the Regress Problem is that this hierarchical
account seems to give an unjustified ontological priority to higher versions of
the self (see Thalberg 1978). Marilyn Friedman has argued that it begs the
question to assume some sort of uncaused “true self” at the top of the
hierarchical pyramid. In order to give a procedural account that would avoid
these objections, Friedman has proposed an integration model in which desires
of different orders ought to be integrated together, rather than being
constructed in a pyramid (Friedman 1986).
iii. Coherentist Accounts
Part of the appeal of understanding autonomy is not simply in explaining
how we make decisions, but because the idea of autonomy suggests something
about how we identify ourselves, what we identify with. For Frankfurt, we
identify with a lower level desire if we have a second order volition endorsing
it. However, our second order volitions don’t necessarily represent us — we may
have no reason for them, which Frankfurt acknowledges.
This concern drives some of the other approaches to personal autonomy,
such as Laura Ekstrom’s coherentist account (Ekstrom 1993). Since autonomy is
self-governance, it stands to reason that in order to understand autonomous
agency, we must clarify our notion of the self and hence what counts as the
self’s own reasons for acting; she argues that this will help avoid the Regress
Problem and the Ab Initio Problem.
Ekstrom’s account of self is based on the endorsement of preferences. An
agent has a preference if he or she holds a certain first level desire to be
good; it is similar to a second order volition for Frankfurt. It presupposes
higher level states since they are the result of an agent’s higher order
reflection about the agent’s desires with regard to goodness. A self, then, is
a particular character with certain beliefs and preferences which have been
endorsed in a process of self-reflection, and the ability to reshape those
beliefs and preferences in light of self-evaluation. The true self includes
those beliefs and preferences which cohere together; that coherence itself
gives them authorization. A preference is thus endorsed if it coheres with the
agent’s character.
Michael Bratman develops a similar account, arguing that our personal
identity is partly constituted by the organizing and coordinating function of
our long-range plans and intentions (Bratman 2007, 5). Our decisions are
autonomous or self-governing with respect to these plans.
This is, of course, only a very brief account of some of the literature
on proceduralist accounts of autonomy, and it omits the various defenses of the
hierarchical model and the objections to Friedman’s, Christman’s, and others’
formulations. But it should be enough to make clear the way in which theorists
offering these accounts strive to ensure that no particular view of what
constitutes a flourishing human life is imported into their accounts of
autonomy. Autonomy is just one valued human property amongst others, and need
not do all the work of describing human flourishing (Friedman 2003).
b. Substantive Accounts
Some doubt, however, that proceduralist accounts are adequate to capture
autonomous motivation and action, or to rule out actions that or agents who we
would hesitate to call autonomous. Substantive accounts of autonomy, of which
there are both weak and strong varieties, set more requirements for autonomous
actions to count as autonomous. Whether weak or strong, all substantive
accounts posit some particular constraints on what can be considered
autonomous; one example might be an account of autonomy that specifies that we
might not autonomously be able to choose to be enslaved. Susan Wolf offers a
strong substantive account, in which agents must have “normative competency,”
in other words, the capacity to identify right and wrong (Wolf 1990). We do not
need to be metaphysically responsible for ourselves or absolutely self-originating,
but as agents we are morally responsible, and capable of revising ourselves
according to our moral reasoning (Wolf 1987). Similarly, Paul Benson’s early
accounts of autonomy also advocated a strong substantive account, stressing
normative competence, and also the threat of oppressive or inappropriate
socialization to our normative competence and thus to our autonomy (Benson
1991).
Contemporary Kantians such as Thomas Hill and Christine Korsgaard also
advocate substantive accounts of autonomy. Korsgaard argues that we have
practical identities which guide us and serve as the source of our normative
commitments (Korsgaard 1996). We have multiple such identities, not all of
which are moral, but our most general practical identity is as a member of the
“kingdom of ends,” our identity as moral agents. This identity generates
universal duties and obligations. Just as Kant called autonomy our capacity for
self-legislation, so too Korsgaard calls autonomy our capacity to give
ourselves obligations to act based on our practical identities. Since one of
these is a universal moral identity, autonomy itself thus has substantive
content.
Autonomy, for Hill, means that principles will not simply be accepted
because of tradition or authority, but can be challenged through reason. He
acknowledges that in our society we do not experience the kind of consensus
about values and principles that Kant supposed ideally rational legislators
might possess, but argues that it is still possible to bear in mind the
perspective of a possible kingdom of ends. Human dignity, the idea of humanity
as an end in itself, can represent a shared end regardless of background or
tradition (Hill 2000, 43-45).
Substantive accounts have been criticized for conflating personal and
moral autonomy and for setting too high a bar for autonomous action. If too
much is expected of autonomous agents’ self-awareness and moral reflection,
then can any of us be truly said to be autonomous (see for example Christman
2004 and Narayan 2002)? Does arguing that agents living under conditions of
oppressive socialization have reduced autonomy help set a standard for
promotion of justice, or does it overemphasize their diminished capacity
without encouraging and promoting the capacities that they do have? This
interplay between our socialization and our capacity for autonomy is
highlighted in the relational autonomy literature, covered below.
In order to come to some middle ground between substantive and
procedural accounts, Paul Benson has also suggested a weak substantive account,
which does not specify any content, but sets the requirement that the agent
must regard himself or herself as worthy to act; in other words, that the agent
must have self-trust, self-respect (Benson 1991). This condition serves to
limit what behavior can be deemed autonomous and to bring it in line with our
intuition that a mind-controlled or utterly submissive agent is not acting
autonomously, while not ruling out the agent’s ability to decide what values he
or she wants to live by.
3. Feminist Philosophy of
Autonomy
a. Feminist Criticisms of
Autonomy
Feminist philosophers have been critical of concepts and values
traditionally seen to be gender neutral, finding that when examined they reveal
themselves to be masculine (see Jaggar 1983, Benjamin 1988, Grimshaw 1986,
Harding and Hintikka 2003, and Lloyd 1986). Autonomy has long been coded
masculine and associated with masculine ideals, despite being something which
women have called for in their own right. Jessica Benjamin argues that while we
are formally committed to equality, “gender polarity underlies such familiar
dualisms as autonomy and dependency” (Benjamin 1988, 7). There has been some
debate over whether autonomy is actually a useful value for women, or whether
it has been tarnished by association.
Gilligan’s criticisms of autonomy have already been covered, but
Benjamin writes along similar lines that:
The ideal of the autonomous individual could only be created by
abstracting from the relationship of dependency between men and women. The
relationships which people require to nurture them are considered private, and
not truly relationships with outside others. Thus the other is reduced to an
appendage of the subject – the mere condition of his being – not a being in her
own right. The individual who cannot recognize the other or his own dependency
without suffering a threat to his identity requires the formal, impersonal
principle of rationalized interaction, and is required by them. (Benjamin 1988,
197)
Benjamin ultimately argues that the entire structure of recognition
between men and women must be altered in order to permit an end to domination.
Neither Gilligan nor Benjamin addresses the possibility of reformulating the
notion of autonomy itself, but each sees it as essentially linked with
individualism and separation. Sarah Hoagland is more emphatic: she openly
rejects autonomy as a value, referring to it as “a thoroughly noxious concept”
as it “encourages us to believe that connecting and engaging with others limits
us” (Hoagland 1988, 144).
These criticisms have been countered, however, by feminists looking to
retain the value of autonomy, who argue that the critics conflate the ideal of
“autonomy” with that of “substantive independence.” Autonomy, while it has
often been associated with individualism and independence, does not necessarily
entail these. Most feminist criticism of autonomy is based on the idea that
autonomy implies a particular model or expectation of the self. Marilyn
Friedman and John Christman, however, point out that the proceduralist notion
of autonomy which is the focus of contemporary philosophical attention does not
have such an implication, but is metaphysically neutral and value neutral
(Friedman 2000, 37-46; Christman 1995).
b. Relational Autonomy
A feminist attempt to rehabilitate autonomy as a value, and to further
underscore the contingency of its relationship to atomistic individualism or
independence, emerges in the growing research on “relational autonomy”
(Nedelsky 1989, Mackenzie and Stoljar 2000). It addresses the challenge of
balancing agency with social embeddedness, without promoting an excessively
individualistic liberal atomism, or denying women the agency required to
criticize or change their situation. The feminist work on relational autonomy
attempts to capture the best of the available positions.
It is worth noting first, for clarity, that there are two levels of
relationality at work within relational autonomy: social and relational sources
of values, goals, and commitments, and social and relational commitments
themselves. While all acknowledge that relationality at both levels is not
incompatible with autonomy, not all accounts of relational autonomy require
that we pursue social and relational commitments. For instance, on Marilyn
Friedman’s account, a person could autonomously choose to be a hermit, despite
having been brought up in a family and in a society and having been shaped by
that upbringing (Friedman 2003, 94). However other relational autonomy
theorists are skeptical about neatly separating the two, because they note that
even our unchosen relationships still affect our self-identity and opportunities.
They argue that while we need not pursue relationships, we cannot opt out
entirely. Anne Donchin demonstrates this with regard to testing for genetically
inherited disease (Donchin 2000).
In general, on relational autonomy accounts, autonomy is seen as an
ideal by which we can measure how well an agent is able to negotiate his or her
pursuit of goals and commitments, some of which may be self-chosen, and some
the result of social and relational influences. Social and relational ties are
examined in terms of their effect on an agent’s competency in this negotiation:
some give strength, others create obstacles, and others are ambiguous. The
primary focus of most relational autonomy accounts, however, tends to be less
on procedure and more on changing the model of the autonomous self from an
individualistic one to one embedded in a social context.
4. Autonomy in Social and
Political Context
The value of autonomy can be seen in its social and political context.
The idea that our decisions, if made autonomously, are to be respected and
cannot be shrugged off, is a valuable one. It concerns the legitimacy of our
personal decisions in a social, political, and legislative context.
a. Autonomy and Political Theory
The importance and nature of the value of autonomy is debated within
political theory, but is generally intertwined with the right to pursue one’s
interests without undue restriction. Discussions about the value of autonomy
concern the extent of this right, and how it can be seen as compatible with
social needs.
Kant described the protection of autonomy at the political level as
encapsulated in the principle of right: that each person had the right to any
action that can coexist with the freedom of every other person in accordance
with universal law (Kant 1996, 387). Mill’s On Liberty similarly defends the
rights of individuals to pursue their own personal goals, and emphasizes the
need for being one’s own person (Mill 1956). On his view, this right prohibits
paternalism, or restrictions or interference with a person of mature age for
his or her own benefit. As Mill writes, “The only part of the conduct of anyone
for which he is amenable to society is that which concerns others. In the part
which merely concerns himself, his independence is, of right, absolute. Over
himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign” (Mill 1956,
13).
Non-interference is generally seen as key to political autonomy; Gerald
Gaus specifies that “the fundamental liberal principle” is “that all
interferences with action stand in need of justification” (Gaus 2005, 272). If
any paternalistic interference is to be permitted, it is generally restricted
to cases where the agent is not deemed to be autonomous with respect to a
decision (see for example Dworkin 1972); autonomy serves as a bar to be reached
in order for an agent’s decisions to be protected (Christman 2004). The
question is then how high the bar ought to be set, and thus what individual
actions count as autonomous for the purposes of establishing social policy.
Because of this, there is a strong connection between personal and political
autonomy.
Further, there is also a connection between political liberalism and
content-neutral accounts of autonomy which do not require any predetermined
values for the agent to be recognized as autonomous. As Christman and Anderson
point out, content-neutral accounts of autonomy accord with liberalism’s model
of accommodating pluralism in ways of life, values, and traditions (Christman
and Anderson 2005).
The framework of seeing the value of political autonomy in terms of
protecting individual choices and decisions, however, has been criticized by
those who argue that it rests on an inadequate model of the self.
Communitarians such as Michael Sandel criticize the model of the
autonomous self implicit in liberal political theory, arguing that it does not
provide an adequate notion of the human person as embedded within and shaped by
societal values and commitments. Procedural accounts of autonomous
decision-making do not adequately recognize the way our relational commitments
shape us. We do not choose our values and commitments from the position of
already being autonomous individuals; in other words, the autonomous self does not
exist prior to the values and commitments that constitute the basis for its
decisions. To deliberate in the abstract from these values and commitments is
to leave out the self’s very identity, and that which gives meaning to the
deliberation (Sandel 1998).
Feminist scholars have agreed with some of the communitarian criticism,
but also caution that the values and commitments that communitarians appeal to
may not be ones that are in line with feminist goals, in particular those
values that concern the role and makeup of the family (Okin 1989 and Weiss
1995).
Another criticism of the dominant model of autonomy within political
theory is made by Martha Fineman, who argues for the need to rethink the
conceptions of autonomy that undergird legal and governmental policies in order
to better recognize our interdependence and the dependence of all of us upon
society (Fineman 2004, 28-30). While not drawing on the philosophical
literature on personal autonomy or relational autonomy, but rather drawing upon
sociological theories and accounts of legal and government policy, she traces
the historical and cultural associations of autonomy with individuality and
masculinity, and argues the need to see that real human flourishing includes
dependency.
Recognizing the different levels of autonomy at play within the
political sphere as a whole can help to clarify what is at stake, and to avoid
one-sided accounts of autonomy or the autonomous self. Rainer Forst outlines
five different conceptions of autonomy that can combine into a multidimensional
account (Forst 2005). The first is moral autonomy, in which an agent can be
considered autonomous as long as he or she “acts on the basis of reasons that
take every other power equally into account” and which are “justifiable on the
basis of reciprocally and generally binding norms” (Forst 2005, 230). Even
though this is an interpersonal norm, it is relevant to the political, argues
Forst, because it promotes the mutual respect needed for political liberty.
Ethical autonomy concerns a person’s desires in the quest for the good life, in
the context of the person’s values, commitments, relationships, and
communities. Legal autonomy is thus the right not to be forced into a
particular set of values and commitments, and is neutral toward them. Political
autonomy concerns the right to participate in collective self-rule, exercised
with the other members of the relevant community. Finally, social autonomy
concerns whether an agent has the means to be an equal member of this
community. Attending to social autonomy helps to demonstrate the responsibility
of members of the community to consider each other’s needs, and to evaluate
political and social structures in terms of whether they serve to promote the
social autonomy of all of the members. Forst argues that ultimately “citizens
are politically free to the extent to which they, as freedom-grantors and
freedom-users, are morally, ethically, legally, politically, and socially
autonomous members of a political community … Rights and liberties therefore
have to be justified not only with respect to one conception of autonomy but
with a complex understanding of what it means to be an autonomous person”
(Forst 2005, 238).
Whether or not one agrees with this particular way of dividing the
conceptions of autonomy, or with the particular explanation of the details of
any of the conceptions, Forst’s account highlights the way that understanding
the contribution of autonomy to political theory involves a multifaceted
approach. It is of limited use to say that citizens are autonomous because they
have the right to vote, if their material needs are not met, or if they are not
free in their choice of values or ethical commitments. Taking ethical autonomy into consideration
can help to meet some of the concerns raised above by communitarian and
feminist critics of autonomy; meanwhile, taking legal autonomy into account
alongside ethical autonomy can help to provide the bulwark of protection
against oppressive traditions that feminists are concerned about.
This can also be related to the work done by Martha Nussbaum and Amartya
Sen on the capabilities approach to human rights, in which societies are called
upon to ensure that all human beings have the opportunity to develop certain
capabilities; agents then have a choice whether or not to develop them (see for
example Sen 1999 and Nussbaum 2006). The
kind of political autonomy granted to subjects, then, depends on their ability
to cultivate these various capabilities within a given society.
b. Autonomy and Bioethics
In applied ethics, such as bioethics, autonomy is a key value. It is
appealed to by both sides of a number of debates, such as the right to free
speech in hate speech versus the right to be free from hate speech (Mackenzie
and Stoljar 2000, 4). There is a lack of consensus, however, on how autonomy
ought to be used: how much rationality it requires, whether it merely involves
the negative right against interference or whether it involves positive duties
of moral reflection and self-legislation.
Autonomy has long been an important principle within biomedical ethics.
For example, in the Belmont report, published in 1979 in the United States,
which articulates guidelines for experimentation on human subjects, the
protection of subjects’ autonomy is enshrined in the principle of “respect for
persons.” One of the three key principles of the Report, it states that
participants in trials ought to be treated as autonomous, and those with
diminished autonomy (due to cognitive or other disabilities or illnesses) are
entitled to protection. The way this principle is to be applied takes shape in
the form of informed consent, as the Report presumes that this is the best way
to protect autonomy.
One of the standard textbooks in biomedical ethics, Principles of Biomedical
Ethics by Tom L. Beauchamp and James F. Childress, defends four principles for
ethical decision-making, of which “respect for autonomy” is the first, even
though it is not intended to override other moral considerations. The principle can be seen as both a negative
and a positive obligation. The negative obligation for health care
professionals is that patients’ autonomous decisions should not be constrained
by others. The positive obligation calls for “respectful treatment in
disclosing information and fostering autonomous decision-making” (Beauchamp and
Childress 2001, 64).
Beauchamp and Childress accept that a patient can autonomously choose to
be guided by religious, traditional, or community norms and values. While they
acknowledge that it can be difficult to negotiate diverse values and beliefs in
sharing information necessary for decision-making, this does not excuse a
failure to respect a patient’s autonomous decision: “respect for autonomy is
not a mere ideal in health care; it is a professional obligation. Autonomous
choice is a right, not a duty of patients” (Beauchamp and Childress 2001, 63).
Autonomy is also important within the disability rights movement. Within
the disability rights movement, the slogan, “Nothing about us without us” is a
call for autonomy or self-determination (see Charlton 1998). It goes beyond merely
rejecting having decisions made for people with disabilities by others, but
also speaks to the desire for empowerment and recognition as being agents
capable of self-determination.
The relational approach to autonomy has become popular in the spheres of
health care ethics and disability theory. The language of relational autonomy
has been helpful in reframing the dichotomy between strict independence and
dependence and providing a way of framing the relationship between a person
with a disability and his or her caretaker or guardian. It has also been argued
that a relational approach to patient autonomy provides a better model of the
decision-making process.
Criticisms of a rationalistic and individualistic ideal of autonomy and
the development of the idea of relational autonomy have been taken up within
the mainstream of biomedical ethics. In response to criticism that early
editions of their textbook on biomedical ethics had not paid adequate heed to
intimate relationships and the social dimensions of patient autonomy, Beauchamp
and Childress emphasize that they “aim to construct a conception of respect for
autonomy that is not excessively individualistic (neglecting the social nature
of individuals and the impact of individual choices and actions on others), not
excessively focused on reason (neglecting the emotions), and not unduly
legalistic (highlighting legal rights and downplaying social practices)”
(Beauchamp and Childress, 2001, 57).
Their account of autonomy, however, has still been criticized by Anne
Donchin as being a “weak concept” of relational autonomy (Donchin 2000). While
they do not deny that selves are developed within a context of community and
human relationships, agents are still assumed to have consciously chosen their
beliefs and values and to be capable of detaching themselves from relationships
at will (Donchin 2000, 238). A strong concept of relational autonomy, on the
other hand, holds that “there is a social component built into the very meaning
of autonomy,” and that autonomy “involves a dynamic balance among
interdependent people tied to overlapping projects” (Donchin 2000, 239). The
autonomous self is one “continually remaking itself in response to
relationships that are seldom static,” and which “exists fundamentally in relation
to others” (Donchin 2000, 239). Donchin argues that it is the strong concept of
relational autonomy that offers the most helpful account of decision-making in
health care.