John
of Paris, also called John the Deaf or John Quidort, French Jean de
Paris, Jean le Sourd, or Jean Quidort, medieval Latin Johannes de
Soardis (born c. 1255, Paris, France—died Sept. 22, 1306, Bordeaux,
Gascony [France]) Dominican monk, philosopher, and theologian who
advanced important ideas concerning papal authority and the
separation of church and state and who held controversial views on
the nature of the Eucharist.
A
lecturer at the University of Paris and the author of several works
defending the doctrines of St. Thomas Aquinas, he was condemned in
1286 for some of his theological propositions but cleared himself by
further explanation.
In
De potestate regia et papali (c. 1302; “On Royal and Papal
Powers”), he held that church and state both derived power from God
but were independent of each other, the church serving spiritual ends
and the state serving secular ends. The pope could intervene in
secular matters only if the moral or theological order was involved.
John also held that since the pope was elected by men, he could be
removed by men for good reason. De potestate, directed against the
extreme papal claims of Pope Boniface VIII, was a valuable
contribution to theology.
In
his eucharistic doctrines expressed in Determinatio (1304), John
suggested an alternative to transubstantiation, namely, the
proposition that the Person of Christ somehow enters into a kind of
hypostatic, or essential, union with the material elements. John’s
heterodoxy was censured, and he was sentenced to perpetual silence;
he died before his appeal to Pope Clement V could be decided.
John
of Paris reasserts the traditional distinction between ownership and
rulership. The fact that a ruler adjudicates property disputes does
not make him supreme owner. A community (a state, or the Church, or
particular communities) acquires property only from individuals, and
the head of the community is the administrator of the community's
property, not its owner. This is true also of the Pope, who does not
have unrestricted power over Church property, still less over the
properties of lay people (pp. 96–105).[80] John's assumption that
original appropriation is by individuals, and his remark that
individuals acquire property by “labour and industry” (pp. 86,
103), have led to suggestions that he anticipated Locke's theory of
property. However, John indicates that individuals acquire property
under human law (pp. 148, 154, 225–6) which is the view traditional
among medieval theologians, following Augustine . Property is
acquired under human law, but it is acquired by individuals, not
directly by rulers.
As
for rulership, John argues that the Pope cannot be the supreme
temporal ruler because the spiritual and temporal powers should be
held by different persons. John gives the traditional reasons ,
emphasizing the argument that the priest should be exclusively
devoted to spiritual affairs (pp. 117–8). The temporal power is not
established by, or in any way caused by, the spiritual power. Both
come from God, but neither comes through the other. The spiritual is
in some sense superior, but not as being the cause of the temporal
power (pp. 93, 192). The basis of the distinction between the two
powers is not subject matter or ends, but means. Each power is
limited to its own appropriate means of action; the secular power
uses natural means, the Church uses supernatural means (pp. 142–61).
This is very much like Thomas Aquinas's picture of two powers leading
mankind toward the goals of human life in ordered hierarchy, one
using natural means and the other supernatural. Thomas infers from
the fact that the Church is concerned with the highest end the
conclusion that the Pope ought to direct the secular ruler . John
explicitly rejects this line of argument. Teaching is a spiritual
function, but in a household the teacher does not direct the
physician. The physician exercises a higher art than the pharmacist,
but, though the physician guides the pharmacist, he cannot give
authoritative directions or dismiss the pharmacist. Such officials in
a great household do not direct one another, but are all under the
direction of the head of the family. Similarly both Pope and prince
derive their authority from God, who sets the limits of their power,
and he has not subordinated one to the other (pp. 182, 184–6, 93).
No comments:
Post a Comment