Feminist epistemology is an outgrowth of both feminist theorizing about
gender and traditional epistemological concerns. Feminist epistemology is a
loosely organized approach to epistemology, rather than a particular school or
theory. Its diversity mirrors the diversity of epistemology generally, as well
as the diversity of theoretical positions that constitute the fields of gender
studies, women’s studies, and feminist theory. What is common to feminist
epistemologies is an emphasis on the epistemic salience of gender and the use
of gender as an analytic category in discussions, criticisms, and
reconstructions of epistemic practices, norms, and ideals. While feminist
epistemology is not easily and simply characterized, feminist approaches to
epistemology tend to share an emphasis on the ways in which knowers are
particular and concrete, rather than abstract and universalizable. Feminist
epistemologies take seriously the ways in which knowers are enmeshed in social
relations that are generally hierarchical while also being historically and
culturally specific. In addition, feminist epistemologies assume that the ways
in which knowers are constituted as particular subjects are significant to
epistemological problems such as warrant, evidence, justification, and
theory-construction, as well as to our understanding of terms like
“objectivity,” “rationality,” and “knowledge.”
1. Introduction
The themes which characterize feminist engagements with epistemology are
not necessarily unique to feminist epistemologies, since these themes also crop
up in science studies more generally, as well as in social epistemology.
Feminist epistemologies are distinctive, however, in the use of gender as a
category of epistemic analysis and re-construction. Feminist approaches to
epistemology generally have their sources in one or more of the following
traditions: feminist science studies, naturalistic epistemologies, cultural
studies of science, Marxist feminism and related work in and about the social
sciences, object relations theory and developmental psychology, epistemic
virtue theory, postmodernism, hermeneutics, phenomenology, and pragmatism. Many
feminist epistemological projects incorporate more than one of these
traditions. For the sake of this entry, however, particular theorists have been
segregated into these fairly arbitrary categories. The caveat here is that each
particular theorist might just as well have been included under a number of
different categories.
2. Critiques of Rationality and
Dualisms
Work by Susan Bordo (1990) and Genevieve Lloyd (1984) analyzes the ways
in which metaphors of masculinity operate in constructions of ideals of
rationality and objectivity. Drawing on feminist discussions of object
relations theory (Bordo) and of the role of the symbolic imaginary and metaphor
in modern epistemological projects, both Lloyd and Bordo argue that the
operations of the symbolic imaginary are implicated in the metaphysics of
subjectivity and objectivity and in the characterization of epistemic problems
that follow from that metaphysics. The result of the work done by these
feminist historians is that ideals of reason, objectivity, autonomy, and
disinterestedness operating in assumptions about inquiry, as well as the idea
that the “perennial” problems of epistemology are gender neutral are now
revealed to be connected to and constitutive of gender relations.
Bordo’s and Lloyd’s analyses provide resources for feminists working in
science studies, as well as those working in Anglo-American analytic
traditions. Much of the work in feminist epistemology is influenced by these
critiques, and the emphasis that Lloyd especially places on the cognitive role
of metaphor, is a starting point for much feminist work on the role of
“affective” and “literary” aspects of cognition and philosophy more generally.
Susan Hekman’s (1990) work argues that dualisms of nature/culture,
rational/irrational, subject/object, and masculine/feminine underwrite
modernist epistemological projects and that feminist epistemology should aim to
destabilize and deconstruct those dualisms. Hekman argues that such
destablization can only take place if feminists refuse the dichotomous
presuppositions of the modernist project, including the dichotomy of
masculine/feminine and its role in identity ascriptions. The aim, then, of
feminist epistemology is both the eradication of epistemology as a going
concern with issues of truth, rationality, and knowledge and the undermining of
gender categories.
Critics of feminist epistemology have charged that feminist critiques of
rationality amount to a valorization of irrationality, a charge that misses the
point of these critiques. If our ideals of rationality are to be interrogated
and reconstructed, then, presumably, our ideals of irrationality will be so
reconstructed as well, since the operative premise of Bordo’s, Lloyd’s and
Hekman’s analyses are that the dichotomy of rationality and irrationality help
to constitute the dualism of masculine/feminine and vice-versa. Thus, what
critics take to be a valorization of irrationality can only appear so if those
dichotomies remain in place.
3. Feminist Science Studies
Much of the initial work in feminist epistemology grew out of feminist
critiques of, and engagement with, science. This work generally emphasizes the
ways in which science has been marked by gender bias, not only in the fact that
women are seriously underrepresented in the sciences, but also in the ways in
which assumptions about gendered behavior serve an evidential role in dominant
and widely accepted theories in such fields as anthropology, biology, and
psychology (Bleier, (1984), Haraway (1988, 1989), Keller (1983, 1984)).
Harding and Hintikka’s (1983) collection represents early work primarily
in science studies and epistemology but also includes early work that
represents one of the primary and unique contributions of feminist
epistemology: the incorporation of moral and political theory in discussions of
epistemology and science.
The recognition that the process of scientific theory construction and
inquiry essentially involved appeals to extra-scientific values was further
developed by subsequent theorists augmenting the early critiques of gender bias
in science. Rather than claiming that values and politics always compromised
scientific inquiry, feminist theorists such as Nelson (1990), Longino (1990)
and Harding (1986, 1991, 1998) argue that such values are always operating in
evaluations of evidence, justification, and theory-construction and that trying
to develop an epistemology for science that would make it less prone to gender
bias requires the recognition of the ways in which values enter the process of
scientific reasoning. Feminist theorists, thus, turned their attention to
developing epistemologies that would allow for critical evaluation of the
values that are shared, and, thus, often invisible, to inquirers in the
sciences. Nelson’s work, drawing on Quine, develops a holistic approach to
questions about evidence and justification, emphasizing the ways in which
knowledge is held by communities, rather than by individual knowers who are
abstractable members of such communities. Helen Longino argues for the value of
pluralism in the construction of scientific models as a way of making the
values and assumptions of scientific communities accessible for critical
evaluation. Harding uses Marxist analysis to develop a feminist version of
standpoint theory.
What these approaches to feminist science studies emphasize is that good
science is not value-free science, since values are ineradicable from the
process of scientific inquiry and theory-construction. Instead, they argue that
good science is science that can critically evaluate the values and assumptions
that operate epistemically in scientific theory construction and in the ways in
which scientific problems are formulated. Good science is a science that can
develop mechanisms for critically evaluating, not only the results of inquiry,
but also the ways in which those results depend upon a raft of value-laden and
theory-laden assumptions and facts.
Part of the problem with these approaches (with the exception of
standpoint epistemologies, which are discussed in more detail below), however,
is that they have few theoretical resources for dealing with questions about
how such diversity can be brought into scientific theorizing, and how one
could, in principle, exclude groups with commitments or values that are, on the
face of it, anti-scientific (e.g. magic) or unpalatable in other ways (e.g.
Nazi science). If the value of pluralism is that it would allow for the
critical reflection necessary for ensuring that the values and commitments that
enter scientific inquiry are visible, then on what grounds could one exclude,
for example, creationism? Feminist epistemology that draws on work in science
studies has revealed the ways in which it is individuals in communities who
know and how such communities operate with a variety of value commitments that
make knowledge possible. However, the issue about methodological pluralism
remains a difficult one.
a. Feminist Naturalized
Epistemologies
Feminist naturalized epistemologies have developed as a way of taking
account of the fact that knowers are located in “epistemic spaces” and the ways
in which knowledge is more properly understood on a community rather than an
individual model. Naturalism is defined here as an approach to epistemology
that focuses on causal accounts of knowledge, and in the case of feminist
naturalism, these causal accounts also include social, political, and
historical factors. Primarily, feminist naturalism seeks to emphasize the ways
in which cultural and historical factors can enable, rather than distort, knowledge.
Feminist naturalism is itself a rather loosely organized category, with some
approaches privileging scientific naturalism and others placing science within
the broader scope of human epistemic endeavors. Feminist naturalist approaches
by Lynn Hankinson Nelson (1990) and Louise Antony (Antony and Witt 1993) try to
develop Quinean naturalism in ways that are consistent with feminist insights
about the epistemic relevance of gender and social relations; other feminist
epistemologists, such as Elizabeth Potter (1995, 2001), draw on sociological
and historical work (in Potter’s case, specifically work on Robert Boyle) to
develop naturalistic accounts of theory construction and choice. Work by Alison
Wylie (1999) develops feminist naturalistic analyses of the scientific
practices of archaeology. The work of Lorraine Code (1987, 1991, 1995, 1996)
can also be characterized as a form of feminist naturalized epistemology; this
work is discussed in greater detail in the section on Epistemic Virtue Theories
below. Nancy Tuana (2003) has developed Charles Mills’s concept of
“epistemologies of ignorance” by looking at the ways in which ignorance, rather
than knowledge, is constructed by studies of sexuality and public school sex
education programs.
Feminist naturalized approaches, like non-feminist naturalized
approaches, often come to grief over the status of normativity in the
construction of theory, since, traditionally, the naturalistic impulse is to
provide a descriptive account of knowledge. However, without an appeal to the
ways in which sexism, racism, or homophobia might deform knowledge practices,
feminist epistemology would appear to have few resources for arguing that
present cultural and historical conditions should be changed, since there is no
way to show that these are inherently unreliable or objectionable. Feminist
naturalized epistemologies differ in how seriously they take this problem. Some
theorists take the challenge presented by this problem very seriously, while
others argue that it is only a problem if we assume a strong
descriptive/prescriptive or fact/value distinction. Those who take the issue
seriously generally offer solutions that either emphasize the value of
pluralism in epistemic pursuits or argue that the distinction between the normative
and the descriptive is less clear cut than naturalism’s opponents think, thus
allowing the feminist naturalist the normative resources that allow for
internal critique. Furthermore, feminist naturalists often point out that
scientific theories that have been motivated by feminist insights have often
turned out to be more empirically reliable than those which claim to be
normatively neutral.
b. Cultural Studies of Science
Cultural studies of science begin with the assumption that science is a
practice and that practices include both normative and descriptive components
that cannot be easily separated from each other. Feminist cultural studies of
science emphasize the importance of non-relativistic epistemological
commitments and the importance of using revised versions of normative concepts
such as “objectivity” and “evidence.” However, they recognize that, insofar as
science is a practice, these concepts and their normative import are worked out
in practical interactions with the material world, a position that requires
that these concepts be revised in ways that are not committed to
representational theories of mind and truth. Karen Barad (1999) uses an
analysis of the practice of using the scanning tunneling microscope to
emphasize the ways in which the boundaries between subject and object are
relatively permeable and to show the ways in which observation itself is a form
of practice. Her “agential realism” seeks to bridge the gap between descriptive
epistemologies and normative epistemologies on the one hand, and between naïve
realism and social constructivist approaches to scientific objects on the
other.
Donna Haraway’s (1988) work on situated knowledges emphasizes the ways
in which science is a rule-governed form of “story-telling” that aims at getting
at the truth, but the idea of truth she uses here is not that of reality an
sich but a reality that is produced by human material practices. Thus, she
argues “facts” are in fact “artifacts” of scientific inquiry. This does not
make them false, but it does render them bound up with processes of human
production and human needs. Nonetheless, they maintain an ontological
independence to a certain extent; this is the central insight of the analogy to
other kinds of artifacts.
c. Standpoint Theory
Feminist standpoint epistemology initially developed in the social
sciences, primarily in work by Nancy Hartsock (1998) in political science and
by Dorothy Smith in sociology. As a methodology for the social sciences, it
emphasizes the ways in which socially and politically marginalized groups are
in a position of epistemic privilege vis-à-vis social structures. Drawing on
Hegel and Marx, feminist standpoint theorists in the social sciences argue that
those on the “outside” of dominant social and political groups must learn not
only how to get along in their own world, but also how to get along in the
dominant society. Thus, they have an “outsider” status with respect to dominant
groups that allows them to see things about social structures and how they
function that members of the dominant group cannot see.
In philosophy, this theoretical position was developed most thoroughly
by Sandra Harding (1986, 1991, 1998). Harding argues that “starting thought
out” from the lives of the marginalized will lead to the development of new
sets of research questions and priorities, since the marginalized enjoy a
certain epistemic privilege that allows them to see problems differently, or to
see problems where members of a dominant group do not. However, Harding
emphasizes that one need not be a member of a marginalized group in order to be
capable of starting one’s thought from that standpoint. She argues that Hegel
was not a slave and Marx was not a member of the proletariat, yet they both
were able to identify with the standpoint of the slave and with that of the
proletariat. Thereby, they were able to start their thought out from lives very
different from their own.
The concept of the “standpoint” of the marginalized is both what sets
standpoint epistemology apart from a general pluralism as well as the concept
that has provided the most challenges to feminist standpoint theorists. One
does not occupy the “feminist standpoint,” for instance, simply in virtue of
being a woman; the feminist standpoint is an achievement rather than something
one is born with. One comes to occupy the feminist standpoint by engaging in
critical thought about one’s experience and its relationship to larger social
and political structures. By the same token, one need not be a woman in order
to occupy the feminist standpoint, since, like Hegel and Marx, one can come to
identify with that standpoint. However, the claim that social marginalization
confers epistemic privilege seems to depend on a concept of identity that needs
to be grounded in the experience of social marginalization, and this has led to
charges that standpoint epistemology cannot avoid assuming a great deal of
commonality in the experiences of marginalized groups. This has also led to
charges that standpoint epistemology must appeal to an “essential” women’s
experience or to an “essential” marginalized experience. Such an appeal,
implying that there are necessary and sufficient conditions for such
experiences, is considered illegitimate by many feminist and postmodernist
theorists because they take it to imply that there is something about
experience that is “natural” or “given” and that it can serve a foundational
role in identity construction. These theorists are suspicious of the claim that
there are some experiences that all and only women have that can serve as a
basis for identification with that group, arguing that the category of “woman”
is either too fractured or too regulative to do the work that feminist
standpoint theorists and identity theorists need it to do.
4. Developmental Psychology,
Object Relations Theory and the Question of ‘Women’s Ways of Knowing’
Similar charges of “essentialism” have been leveled at feminist
epistemologies that draw on developmental psychology and object relations
theory to develop epistemic norms. This strand has been more influential in
developing feminist moral epistemologies, but it has had some influence on
epistemologies developed in tandem with the science studies strain in feminist
epistemology as well. Carol Gilligan’s (1982) groundbreaking work in
developmental moral psychology in In a Different Voice gave rise to a variety
of feminist moral epistemologies that emphasized relatedness and affect to
counterbalance the traditional emphasis on moral reasoning as a process of
deductive reasoning that takes the reasoner from a moral principle to a
particular moral judgment. In a Different Voice raises the issue of whether and
how reasoning is tied to the practices of child-rearing, through which children
develop gender affiliations and come to live out gendered ideals. Gilligan
argues that the moral reasoning processes that take into account relationships
in determining the right moral action in a given situation, processes which
child development theorists characterized as “immature” or less developed than
reasoning processes that operated deductively, are simply complementary and not
necessarily inferior. Gilligan’s criticism of Kohlberg’s work, however, ties
these reasoning styles to sex: Kohlberg’s studies of moral development and
moral reasoning uses boys almost exclusively. The responses that girls give,
which often invoke the importance of maintaining relationships when posed with
a moral conflict and which emphasize negotiations, are characterized by
Kohlberg and his research team as developmentally prior to the deductive
reasoning that characterizes the boys’ responses. Gilligan conjectures that
girls have more permeable boundaries of the self and are often more concerned
with relationship maintenance as a result of their upbringing and that this
might account for the different “reasoning styles” that seem to attend gender
differences.
Support for this conjecture may be found in object-relations theory.
Object relations theory emphasizes the fact that the cognitive distinctions
that underlie physical object theory, the process of learning to distinguish
between self and other, and the processes of learning language and moral norms
all evolve contemporaneously and are tied to each other in a variety of ways
such that they re-enforce each other. Coming to learn about objects is
connected to coming to learn about what makes one a self and not a thing, and
is, thus, connected to theories of mind and intentionality; coming to learn
about the persistence of physical objects in time and space depends on
developing a sense of an “I” which persists and remains unchanged, even as
perceptions change. Feminists emphasize the fact that while all the
aforementioned cognitive developments are taking place, the development and
re-enforcement of gender ideals and norms is also taking place, overlapping and
helping to constitute the cognitive distinctions. Thus, cognitive ideals and
virtues come to be saturated with, and partly constitutive of, gender norms and
moral norms.
Developmental psychology and object-relations theory, however, are seen
by some feminist epistemologists as troublesome, insofar as they assume certain
kinds of commonalities in child-rearing that transcend class and race
differences. In addition, the claim that women reason differently than men, no
matter what the source of that difference, is thought to be both wrong and
politically retrograde. However, the virtue of these approaches is that they
allow feminist epistemologists to claim that the gender of the reasoner is
epistemically significant, which in turn can support the claim that the fact
that women are absent from particular studies. Alternatively from the practice
of philosophy or science, it means that different ways of thinking about
problems or issues may also be missing as a result of that exclusion.
Some of the ways in which the developmental psychology and
object-relations strain have contributed to feminist epistemologies in both the
sciences and in moral philosophy, however, have relied less on the empirical
claims that there are reasoning differences between men and women. These
approaches take seriously the ways in which certain aspects of human cognition
and reasoning have been tied to women and often devalued as a result, and they
take that symbolic relationship as the starting point for epistemic
investigation. Along these lines, feminist epistemologists analyze the ways in
which testimony operates epistemically while also being embedded in particular
social relations that are often opaque to actors and reasoners. Similarly,
feminist epistemologies have sought to find a place for affect, relationships,
and care in both moral reasoning and in epistemic practices more generally.
This branch of feminist epistemology is covered in the section on epistemic
virtue theories below.
5. Hermeneutics, Phenomenology,
and Postmodernist Approaches
The ways in which Continental philosophical approaches have shaped
feminist epistemologies are both complicated and widespread, and even feminist
epistemologists who are writing primarily in the Anglo-American tradition have
often been influenced by the critical trends in Continental thought. This is
true not only of Marxist-feminist epistemologies described above, but it is
also true of feminist science studies generally and of feminist epistemologies
which draw on developmental psychology and feminist epistemic virtue theory. It
is not unusual to find feminist philosophers who are trained primarily in the
Anglo-American “analytic” tradition who draw on work in hermeneutics,
phenomenology and postmodernism, while feminists who locate their work in these
traditions often cross this boundary as well. Similarly, feminist pragmatism
(discussed below) often draws on both the Anglo-American analytic tradition and
the Continental tradition. It is safe to say that these categories, never
stable in non-feminist philosophy, are even more loosely defined in feminist
philosophy.
Feminist epistemologies that develop out of the Continental tradition
often take as their starting point the need to re-envision and reconstruct the
epistemological project more generally. Drawing on Foucault, Gadamer, and
Habermas, among others, Linda Martín Alcoff (1993, 1996) argues for a
re-orientation of epistemological projects that can take into account the
political nature of truth-claims and knowledge production and can provide
resources for reconstructing normative epistemic concepts such as rationality,
justification, and knowledge.
Continental feminist epistemologies emphasize the ways in which
epistemic practices, norms, and products (e.g. knowledge) are not neutral but
are, in fact, both produced by, and partly-constitutive of, power relations.
However, the claim that knowledge practices and products are not neutral does
not amount to the claim that they are false or distorted, since all knowledge
practices and products are enmeshed in power relations. The ideal of
neutrality, assumed to be essential to good knowledge practices, is, in fact,
itself a political construction. Thus, a re-construction of epistemic value
terms must be a re-construction that recognizes the political nature of
epistemology and epistemic practices. Feminist theorists add to this
theoretical approach an emphasis on the ways in which gender is another, and
different, layer of power relations.
The other aspect of Continental philosophical traditions that has been
used by feminists to introduce and develop an analysis of the epistemic
salience of gender has been the phenomenological tradition and its emphasis on
the “lived body.” Work by Gail Weiss and Elizabeth Grosz (1994), among others,
draws on phenomenology to re-frame epistemological inquiry as well as develops
its theory of the body to undermine the oppositional dualisms that Genevieve
Lloyd (1984), Susan Bordo (1990), and Susan Hekman (1990) identify as
implicated in gender norms and ideals.
Feminist work in the Continental tradition has also led to a critical
evaluation of the centrality of epistemology to philosophy and to a concomitant
critique of feminists who insist on locating their work in the field of
epistemology. A related argument will be addressed below in the section on
pragmatist feminist epistemology. The theoretical impetus that comes from the
Continental tradition, unlike the one that arises in pragmatism, is connected
to the analysis of truth as an instrument of domination, as part of the
constitution and maintenance of hegemonic practices, or as a strategic move to
eliminate conflict and resistance. This is not a position on which there is agreement
among feminist theorists working in the Continental tradition, but the critique
of epistemology has been one of the most important developments to come out of
feminist engagements with this tradition, and that critique has taken a unique
form. Thus, one aspect of feminist Continental epistemology is the attack on
epistemology itself, feminist epistemology included.
6. Feminist Epistemic Virtue
Theory
Epistemic virtue theories generally focus on the ways in which
epistemology and value theory overlap, but feminist versions of these theories
focus on the ways in which gender and power relations come into play in both
value theory and epistemology and, specifically, on the ways in which subjects
are constructed in the interplay of knowledge claims, power relations, and
value theory.
Work on the history of philosophy by feminists has led to critiques of
philosophical assumptions about what constitutes epistemic virtue, particularly
those virtues assumed to be definitive of reason and objectivity. Bordo’s
(1990) and Lloyd’s (1984) work examines the ways in which “maleness” and
“femaleness” operate symbolically in philosophical discussions of conceptual
relationships assumed to be dichotomous, for instance: reason/unreason,
reason/emotion, objectivity/subjectivity, and universality/particularity.
These critical engagements with the history of philosophy have laid the
groundwork for feminist attempts to reconfigure epistemic virtues in ways that
allow for the re-integration of faculties or aspects of knowledge that have
been excluded from analyses of epistemic virtue because of their alignment in
the “imaginary” of philosophy with women or with the forces of irrationality.
Lorraine Code’s work (1987, 1991, 1995, 1996) argues for the epistemic
salience of, among other things, testimony, gossip, and the affective and
political operations according to which identities are constructed and
maintained. Code and other feminists working in this area emphasize the ways in
which social and political forces shape our identities as epistemic authorities
and as rational agents and how these, in turn, lead to a different
understanding of epistemic responsibility.
Code’s work has also been influential in the development of another
strand of feminist epistemology. This strand can be characterized as a version
of naturalism [[that]] takes issue with the ways in which traditional
epistemological paradigms derive from cases of simple and uncontroversial
empirical beliefs. For instance, beliefs like, “I know that I am seeing a tree,”
deform the epistemic landscape. This includes a criticism of the paradigm of
knowledge as propositional and a related criticism of the presumed
individualism of epistemic pursuits. In addition, this naturalistic turn in
feminist epistemology takes issue with the traditional epistemological concern
with the skeptical problem, in most instances simply ignoring it as an
epistemological issue rather than arguing against its importance. The skeptical
problem is often taken to be a problem primarily for individualist
epistemologies that also assume that knowledge is essentially propositional and
that it is to be explained in terms of individual mental states. Since many
feminist epistemic virtue theorists reject all or most of these assumptions,
the skeptical problem cannot get any traction and is consequently ignored in
virtue of its status as a pseudo-problem.
7. Pragmatism and Feminist
Epistemologies
For feminist pragmatist approaches, the skeptical problem becomes a
non-problem as well, but this is in virtue of the major change wrought in
philosophical thinking about knowledge in the wake of Darwin and the
pragmatists. Early pragmatists like John Dewey and William James were already
recognizing that key terms used in epistemological discourse require revision:
terms like “belief” as opposed to “emotion” or “desire,” issues of truth and
reference, and representational theories of belief and knowledge are all
radically de-stabilized by pragmatist thinkers. Richard Rorty’s development of
this theme in the twentieth century led him to conclude that epistemology is
dead and that philosophy is the better for it.
Feminist pragmatists share this suspicion of epistemology, although they
continue to work on issues related to knowledge. However, theorists like
Charlene Haddock Seigfried (1996) argue that since epistemology is importantly
tied to terms for which feminist pragmatists have no use, they ought to see
themselves as doing something other than epistemology.
Feminist pragmatism has its own version of a naturalized epistemology,
but it is a naturalism that, like the naturalism found in feminist epistemic
virtue theories, resists reduction to cognitive psychology or neuroscience.
Instead, and similar to feminist epistemic virtue theories, it begins with the
common problems of knowledge that occur at the crossroads of ordinary
experience. Knowledge and its problems present themselves in the same way that
other social problems present themselves: as opportunities for melioration and
the improvement of life.
The basic epistemic building block for pragmatist feminist approaches is
the organism rather than the mind or the body. “Experience” is more complex
than sensory states, since it is the way in which the organism interacts with
its world, a world that includes not just objects but also social institutions,
relationships, and politics. As a result, knowledge pursuits are already
implicated with values, politics, and bodies.
Pragmatist feminist approaches to accounts of knowledge, thus, share
much with naturalized accounts of epistemology, but the idea of science that
operates in feminist pragmatist theories is science as characterized by Charles
Sanders Peirce, William James, and John Dewey, rather than the characterization
of science as it appears in the analytic tradition of philosophy. There are, of
course, differences among Peirce, James, and Dewey in their characterization of
science, but it is fair to understand their views as underwritten by an
understanding of science as a way of interacting with the world that is also
enmeshed in human values and human endeavors. Feminist pragmatist
epistemologies share this understanding of science, emphasizing its liberatory
project and its role in the melioration of social problems.
Thus, feminist pragmatist epistemological projects attempt to keep our
knowledge endeavors true to the liberatory impulse while also re-configuring
problems of knowledge in terms that take seriously the insights of evolutionary
theory, humanistic empirical psychology, and the understanding of the knowing
subject as an organism whose knowledge endeavors are taken up in both a
material and a social world.
No comments:
Post a Comment